1 / 19

What is “Animal Rights”?

What is “Animal Rights”?. It’s the philosophy of allowing nonhuman animals to have the basic rights that all sentient beings desire: the freedom to live a natural life, free from human exploitation, unnecessary pain and suffering, and premature death. Speciesism.

damita
Download Presentation

What is “Animal Rights”?

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. What is “Animal Rights”? It’s the philosophy of allowing nonhuman animals to have the basic rights that all sentient beings desire: the freedom to live a natural life, free from human exploitation, unnecessary pain and suffering, and premature death.

  2. Speciesism is the withholding of these basic rights from nonhuman animals. Discriminating solely on the basis of species is as illegitimate as discriminating on the basis of sex, or race, or the ability to Cha Cha. There is no reason to value some mentally defective human beings coughBushcough more than some nonhuman animals.

  3. Animal Rights is NOT about working for equality between human and nonhuman animals. Different creatures -- women, men, children, animals … need different rights -- access to abortion, voting, room to stretch wings.

  4. From where do AR supporters derive their moral criteria? Logic. At the foundation of a system of ethics are moral axioms, such as “causing unnecessary pain is wrong". Given the set of axioms, methods of reasoning (such as deduction and induction), and empirical facts, it is possible to derive ethical hypotheses. It is in this sense that an ethical statement can be said to be true.

  5. The most fundamental ethical axioms are nearly universally accepted. However, actions from these axioms are not logically concluded. This can be demonstrated by asking a person why he has compassion for human beings. Typically he’ll agree that his compassion does not stem from the fact that humans: 1) do math, 2) speak French, or 3) go bowling. Instead, he’ll say that it stems from the fact that humans can suffer, feel pain, be harmed, etc. It is then easy to show that nonhuman animals can also suffer, etc. The person's inconsistency in not according moral status to nonhumans then stands out starkly.

  6. Logic didn’t impress this guy

  7. The Complete Logicof Animal Rights • Let’s begin with a statement with which most of us agree, and then see if that helps us understand this issue by exploring all logical paths. • Something most of us believe: • It would be morally wrong for anyone to treat us as animals are treated. • (Might we be wrong in that judgment?)

  8. Why do you believe… • …that it would be wrong for someone to perform harmful (painful, fatal) experiments on you to try to cure someone else’s diseases or to increase knowledge in general? What is it about you that makes it wrong to treat you those ways? What ethical hypothesis best explains that fact (if it is a fact)?

  9. An answer: We have moral rights that make it wrong to mistreat us • Moral Rightsare like invisible ‘No Trespassing’ signs; They protect our most fundamental interests in life, avoiding suffering, not being ‘used’ as ‘mere means’, etc. • Rights impose respect: if someone has rights, their interests must be respected; he or she is not a mere ‘thing’ to be used, against her will.

  10. Who has moral rights? • At least, folks like us, we tend to think. • Who is “like us”? Some answers: • 1. ‘Rational’ beings, so a being has rights if, and only if, it is can engage in abstract reasoning. • 2. ‘Intelligent’ beings, so a being has rights if, and only if, it is smart enough. • 3. ‘Autonomous beings,’ so a being has rights if, and only if, it can reflect on its life and decide how to best pursue it. • 4. ‘Beings who have the concept of rights,’ so a being has rights if, and only if, it recognizes that it has rights.

  11. If any of these claims are true • (and rights require sophisticated mental abilities), then none of the following beings are owed respect; they can all be used as mere things: • 1. Human babies • 2. Severely mentally challenged individuals • 3. Alzheimer’s patients • 4. Humans in comas • 5. coughBushcough • If you think any of the above deserve rights, then the previous rationale is refuted.

  12. Another approach to assigning rights • “We have rights, i.e., are owed respect because we are human.” • What do you mean by ‘human’? • Do you mean ‘biologically human’ or having human DNA, or being in the human species? If so, then you are suggesting this: • “A being has rights, if and only if, it is biologically human.”

  13. Using biology to assign moral rights • gives rights to: human organs in a vat • human cells in Petri dish • dead human corpses • very early human fetuses • Furthermore, assigning rights based simply on a physical characteristic is no more ethical than assigning rights to white people, Nazis, or clowns with big ears. If you accept this, then someone else may use similar logic to exclude you from having rights.

  14. A rough hypothesis about moral rights • A being has moral rights – is owed respect and is not a thing to be used for pleasure or even serious benefits for others – if it is conscious, can feel pain and pleasure, and its life can be better and worse for it, from its own point of view.

  15. A consequence of this theory Some animals are conscious, can feel pain and pleasure, and its life can be better and worse for it, from its own point of view. Therefore, they moral have rights on this view: they are not ours to eat, wear, experiment on, or use for entertainment.

  16. Logical Conclusion • If some humans have moral rights, then some animals have moral rights also. • The best reasons to think that humans have rights justifies the claim that animals have rights. • Logical, rational consistency requires this. • Moral rights really have nothing fundamentally to do with biological species.

  17. Responses Response 1: accept the basic argument Response 2: try to argue that it is unsound. To do this: One needs a better hypothesis that explains why humans have the moral rights they do that “covers” all the relevant humans. But, this hypothesis cannot apply to any animals either.

  18. All attempts to do this suffer from these flaws 1. They are wildly implausible and convoluted explanations why we have rights, or: 2. They imply that it’s only a contingent fact, or an accident, that babies and mentally challenged humans have rights. 3. They imply there’s no reason why anyone should not be tortured for fun and that only laws keep them from these actions; they remove “morality” entirely.

  19. Doesn't the Bible give Humanity dominion over animals? Dominion is not the same as tyranny. The Queen of England has dominion over her subjects, but that doesn't mean she can eat them, wear them, or experiment on them. Seeking moral authority from the Bible has two problems: 1. the world has many gods. 2. there are serious problems with literal interpretation of Biblical passages. Here is a list of biblical passages and quotes from biblical scholars that support animal rights: http://www.animalliberationfront.com/Saints/Authors/Quotes/SortQuotesRelig.htm

More Related