1 / 58

CIS 200 Professional and ethical issues in computing Edited by Rawan T. Khasawneh

CIS 200 Professional and ethical issues in computing Edited by Rawan T. Khasawneh. ILOS. What is ethics, and how is it different from morality or moral system? What are the elements that make up a moral system?. Morality. Ethics. Derived from Ethos (Greek ) From Mores (Latin).

tylerburns
Download Presentation

CIS 200 Professional and ethical issues in computing Edited by Rawan T. Khasawneh

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CIS 200 Professional and ethical issues in computing Edited by Rawan T. Khasawneh

  2. ILOS • What is ethics, and how is it different from morality or moral system? • What are the elements that make up a moral system?

  3. Morality • Ethics • Derived from Ethos (Greek) From Mores (Latin). • The study of morality A system of rules and principles Character, Custom, Habit, and Behavior Both tried to answer: Is this behavior ……….

  4. Ethics Definition • The study of morality! • What is morality?! • A system of rules for guiding human conduct, and principles for evaluating those rules • What is the study of morality?!

  5. Moral System • Rules for guiding human conduct • As Moral rules • As Rules of conduct (Two kinds) • Directives • Social policies • As Policies • Have a wide range of application; • Moor (2004) said policies range from formal laws to informal, implicit guidelines for actions. • Moor suggests that every act can be viewed as an instance of a policy.

  6. Two kinds of rules of conduct • Directivesfor guiding our conduct as individuals (at the micro-level) • rules (of conduct) that guide our actions, and thus direct us to behave in certain ways. • direct us in our individual moral choices at the "micro-ethical" level • The level of individual behavior • Rules such as • "Do not steal" • "Do not harm others" • Social policies framed at the macro-level • rules of conduct guide our actions at the "macro-ethical" level • Rules such as • “Proprietary software should not be copied“ • “Software that can be used to invade the privacy of users should not be developed" Both are derived from a set of “core vales” in a moral system Correlation should be noticed!

  7. Moral System • Principles (standards) for evaluating rules of conduct • Example1: • "social utility“ (i.e., promoting the greatest good for the greatest number) ……….. Principle • “Proprietary software should not be copied without permission.“ ……………….. Social policy X Litmus test to evaluate • A policy, X, could be justified (on utilitarian grounds) by showing that following Policy X (i.e., not allowing the unauthorized copying of software) would produce more overall social utility (greater good for society) than permits software to be duplicated freely.

  8. Moral System • Example2: • “Users should not have their privacy violated” … Social policy • Two options of principles: • Social utility • Respect for persons • Litmus test to evaluate

  9. Figure 2-1: Basic Components of a Moral System Rules of Conduct (Action-guiding rules, in the form of either directives or social policies) Principles of Evaluation (Evaluative standards used to justify rules of conduct) Examples include principles such as of social utility and justice as fairness two types Rules for guiding the actions of individuals (micro-level ethical rules) Rules for establishing social policies (macro-level ethical rules) Examples include directives such as:"Do not steal" and "Do not harm others." Examples include social policies such as: "Software should be protected“ and "Privacy should be respected."

  10. Moral issues • Moral dilemma • Not every moral issue (or moral problem) that arises is (also) necessarily a moral dilemma. • Not every dilemma is moral in nature. • A dilemma is a situation where one must choose between two undesirable options, which often leads to one’s having to choose between “the lesser of two evils.” • Example: runaway trolley • Most of the moral concerns/problem that we examine in this text are moral issues

  11. Bernard Gert’s Scheme of a Moral System What kind of a system is a moral system? • Morality: is a system whose purpose is to: • Prevent harm and evils. • Promote human flourishing. • Some other characteristics that define a moral system: • In addition to rules of conduct and principles of evaluation • Public (open and accessible to all) • Informal (like an informal game!) • Each game has a goal and rules that should be know by all players. • One difference: not everyone is required to participate in a game but we are all obligated to participate in a moral system. • Rational (open to reason, no special knowledge) • Impartial (“blindfold of justice”, fair to all)

  12. Table 2-1:  Four Features of Gert’s Moral System Public The rules are known to all of the members. Informal The rules are informal, not like formal laws in a legal system. Rational The system is based on principles of logical reason accessible to all its members. Impartial The system is not partial to any one group or individual.

  13. Figure 2-2: Components of a Moral System Religion Philosophy Law Grounds for justifying moral principles Principles of Evaluation  Rules of Conduct Moral principles and rules Source of moral rules Core Values

  14. The Role of Values in a Moral System • Definition • Comes from Latin valere • “Having worth or being of worth” • “Objects of our desires or interests” • Ex. Happiness, love, and freedom • Types of values • Intrinsic values • They are valued for their own sake • Ex. Life, happiness • Instrumental values • Serve some further end or good • Ex. Automobiles, computers, and money • “Core values are basic to a society’s flourishing and possibly to the society survival”

  15. Values (continued) • Types of values: • Moral values • Reason (logic) informs us that it is in our interest to develop values that promote our own survival, happiness, and flourishing as individuals. • Ex. Impartiality, justice, fairness • Non moral values • When used to further only our own self-interests • Things that individuals are free to choose • Ex. Playing a game, eating a good meal, reading,….,etc. • Our basic moral values are derived from core non-moral values.

  16. Three Schemes for Grounding the Evaluative Rules in a Moral System • The principles are grounded in one of three different kinds of schemes: • religion; • law; • philosophical ethics. • We will see how a particular moral principle or rule – e.g., “Do not steal” –can be justified from the vantage point of each scheme.

  17. Approach #1: Grounding Moral Principles in a Religious System • Consider the following rationale for why stealing is morally wrong: Stealing is wrong because it offends God or because it violates one of God's (Ten) Commandments (a supreme authority).

  18. Approach #2: Grounding Moral Principles in a Legal System An alternative rationale would be: Stealing is wrong because it violates the law. • Here the grounds for determining why stealing is wrong are not tied to religion. • If stealing violates a law in a particular nation or jurisdiction, then the act of stealing can be declared to be wrong independent of any religious beliefs that one may or may not happen to have. • External sanctions

  19. Approach #3: Grounding Moral Principles in a Philosophical System of Ethics • A third way of approaching the question is: Stealing is wrong because it is wrong (independent of any form of external authority or any external sanctions). • On this view, the moral "rightness" or "wrongness" of stealing is not grounded in some external authoritative source. • It does not appeal to an external authority, either theological or legal, for justification.

  20. Approach # 3 Continued • Many philosophers and ethicists have argued that reason alone is sufficient to show that stealing is wrong. • They argue that reason can inform us that there is something either in the act of stealing itself, or in the consequences that result from this kind of act, that makes stealing morally wrong.

  21. Approach # 3 Continued • In the case of both law and religion, • specific sanctions against stealing exist in the form of punishment. • In the case of (philosophical) ethics, • the only sanction would be in the form of social disapproval, and possibly social ostracism. • there is no punishment in a formal sense. • External conditions or factors, in the form of sanctions, are irrelevant.

  22. Discussion Stoppers as "Roadblocks" to Moral Discourse • Discussion stoppers can be articulated in terms of the following four questions:  • People disagree about morality; so how can we reach agreement on moral issues? • Who am I/Who are we to judge others and to impose my/our values on others? • Isn't morality simply a private matter? • Isn't morality simply a matter that different cultures and groups should determine for themselves?

  23. Ethical Theories • Structure • Characteristics • Types

  24. Theory in science Theory in general • guides us in our investigations • provides us with some general principles and structures to analyze our data. Ethical theories ‘like any scientific theory’ • provide a framework for analyzing issues.

  25. “The individual elements of the theory must fit together to form a unified whole” Coherent “Its component parts cannot contradict each other” Consistent A good theory should be “A theory must be able to apply broadly to a wide range of actions” Comprehensive “The theory cannot simply address individual symptoms peculiar to specific cases, while ignoring general principles that would apply in similar cases. “ Systematic

  26. Why Do we Need Ethical Theories? Ethical theories can help us to avoid inconsistent reasoning in our thinking about moral issues and moral dilemmas. Ex. Victims of the trolley accident are taken to the hospital and only limited resources are available to the accident victims!!!

  27. Utilitarianism “An individual act (X) or a social policy (Y) is morally permissible if the consequences that result from (X) or (Y) produce the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of persons affected by the act or policy.”

  28. Utilitarianism • It is founded on the ability to predict the consequences of an action. To a utilitarian, the choice that yields the greatest benefit to the most people is the choice that is ethically correct • Social utility principle should be used to determine morality • can be measured by the amount of happiness produced for society as a whole. • So if choosing between acts A or B, the morally correct action will be the one that produces the most desirable outcome. • Whose outcome?! • Greatest number of individuals or the majority

  29. Utilitarianism (continued) • Utilitarians such as Jeremy Bentham assume: • all people desire happiness; • happiness is an intrinsic good that is desired for its own sake.

  30. Utilitarianism (continued) • According to John Stuart Mill: The only possible proof showing that something is audible is that people actually hear it; the only possible proof that something is visible is that people actually see it; and the only possible proof that something is des- ired is that people actually desire it.

  31. Act Utilitarianism “Anact, X, is morally permissible if the consequences produced by doingX result in the greatest good for the greatest number of persons affected by X”

  32. Act Utilitarianism criticisms Critics • Reject the emphasis on the consequence of individual acts. • Point out that in our day-to-day activities, we tend not to deliberate on each individual action as if that action were unique. • Argue that we are inclined to deliberate on the basis of certain principles or general rules that guide our behavior.

  33. Rule Utilitarianism “An act, X, is morally permissible if the consequences of following the general rule (Y), of which act X is an instance, would bring about the greatest good for the greatest number”

  34. Rule Utilitarianism criticisms Critics • Tend to attack one or both of the following aspects of utilitarian theory: • Morality is ultimately tied to happiness or pleasure • Morality can ultimately be determined by consequences (of either acts or policies). • Argue that morality can be grounded neither in consequences nor in happiness. • Argue that some alternative criterion or standard is needed

  35. Immanuel Kant Deontology • morality must ultimately be grounded in the concept of duty or obligations that humans have to one another. • morality can never be grounded in the consequences of human actions. • morality has nothing to do with the promotion of happiness or the achievement of desirable consequences. • rejects utilitarianism in particular, and all consequentialist ethical theories in general. • For example, he points out that, in some instances, performing our duties may result in our being unhappy and may not necessarily lead to consequences that are considered desirable. • “Deon” is a Greek root which means duty. • defends his ethical theory on the grounds that: • humans are rational, autonomous agents • human beings are ends-in-themselves, and not means to ends.

  36. Is there a rule or principle that can be used in an objective and impartial way to determine the basis for our moral obligations? Yes, there is! It is called “categorical imperative ” • Categorical imperative has a number of variations: • “Act always on that maxim or principle (or rule) which ensures that all individuals will be treated as ends-in-themselves and never merely as a means to an end” • “Always act on that maxim or principle (or rule) which can be universally binding, without exception, for all human beings” Rule Deontology

  37. In such as system, every individual would be treated fairly since the same rules would apply universally to all persons. • Impartiality • Universality

  38. Rule Deontology criticisms Critics • it cannot help us in cases where we have two or more conflicting duties. • ex. we have duties to both keep promises and to tell the truth, and sometimes we encounter situations in which we are required either to: • tell the truth and break a promise or • to keep a promise and tell a lie. • Kant does not provide us with a mechanism for resolving such conflicts.

  39. David Ross Act Deontology • argues that when two or more moral duties clash, we have to look at the individual situation (or “circumstance”) to determine which duty is overriding. • Like act utilitarians, Ross stresses the importance of analyzing individual actions and situations to determine the morally appropriate course of action to take. • Unlike utilitarians, Ross believes that we must not consider the consequences of actions when deliberating over which course of action morally trumps or outweighs another. • Like Kant (and deontologists in general), Ross believes that the notion of duty is ultimate criterion for determining morality. • Unlike Kant, however, Ross does not believe that blind adherence to certain maxims or rules can work in every case for determining which duties we must ultimately carry out.

  40. David Ross Act Deontology • believes that we have certain prima facie (or self-evident) duties which, "all things being equal," we must follow. • provides a list of prima facie duties such as honesty, benevolence, justice, etc. • For example, we have a prima facie duty not to lie and a prima facie duty to keep a promise. • If there are no conflicts in a given situation, then each prima facie duty is also an actual duty. • believes that we can determine what our overriding duty is in a particular situation by using a two-step deliberative process, in which we: • reflect on the competing prima facie duties, • weigh the evidence at hand to determine which course of action would be required in a particular circumstance.  

  41. Contract-based ethical theories

  42. Contract-based ethical theories From the perspective of social-contract theory, a moral system comes into being by virtue of certain contractual agreements between individuals.

  43. Contract-based ethical theories • One of the earliest versions of a contract-based ethical theory can be found in the writings of Thomas Hobbes. • One virtue of the social-contract model is that it gives us a motivation for being moral. • For example, it is in our individual self-interest to develop a moral system with rules (Pojman 2006). • This type of motivation for establishing a moral system is absent in both the utilitarian or deontological theories. • So a contract-based ethical theory would seem to have one advantage over both.

  44. Critics Criticism of Social Contract Theory point out that social-contract theory provides for only a minimalist morality. For example, it is minimalist in the sense that we are obligated to behave morally only where an explicit or formal contract exists (Pojman 2006). So if I have no express contract with you, or if a country like the U.S. has no explicit contract with a developing nation, there is no moral obligation for me to help you, or no obligation for the U.S. to come to the aid of that developing nation. We can think of many situations involving morality where there are no express contracts or explicit laws describing our obligations to each other. • Most of us also believe that in at least some of these cases, we are morally obligated to help others when it is in our power to do so.

  45. Doing good • Doing no harm Minimalist morality!

  46. Criticism of Social Contract Theory (Continued) Rights-based contract theories

  47. Freedom from interference; an entitlement to be left alone. • Negative rights • simply that one has the right not to be interfered with in carrying out the privileges associated with that right. Having a negative right to something means: • For example, your right to vote and your right to own a computer are both negative rights. • has the right (and the expectation) not to be interfered with in exercising that right – e.g., the right to vote in a particular election or the right to purchase a computer. The holder of a negative right you cannot demand (or even expect) that others must either physically transport you to the voting polls, or provide you with a computer if you cannot afford to purchase one.

More Related