1 / 81

Not So Cheap Talk: Costly and Discrete Communication

Not So Cheap Talk: Costly and Discrete Communication. John Smith Rutgers University-Camden w/ Johanna Hertel. Introduction. Reality is complex and nuanced Often use words to communicate information about reality Single word can rarely convey entire extent of the complex reality

jalila
Download Presentation

Not So Cheap Talk: Costly and Discrete Communication

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Not So Cheap Talk: Costly and Discrete Communication John Smith Rutgers University-Camden w/ Johanna Hertel

  2. Introduction • Reality is complex and nuanced • Often use words to communicate information • about reality • Single word can rarely convey • entire extent of the complex reality • More “things” • than “words” • Can approach desired complexity • by constructing more elaborate and complex statements • comes at a cost to the sender

  3. Tyson Hartwig • Coauthor of experimental paper • Undergrad who • now at UBC grad school • Our paper accepted at Stony Brook • I wanted feedback • I could not attend • Tyson could • I know much more about • theory and • presenting

  4. Tyson Hartwig • We have identical preferences over his performance • Effectively communicate • Look competent • Help get him into grad school • Q: Why didn’t I communicate • EVERYTHING relevant to the presentation? • A: Communication is costly

  5. Cheap Talk • Crawford and Sobel (1982) • Informed sender • Unformed receiver • Sender to take action which affects both • Communication is costless • Different preferences over action • Equilibria where meaningful communication

  6. Related Literature: Cheap Talk • Morgan and Stocken (2003) • Uncertainty divergence of preferences • Fischer and Stocken (2001) • Sender imperfect information about state • Blume, Board and Kawamura (2007) • Communication errors • Same spirit as these

  7. Related Literature: NITS • Many equilibria in Crawford and Sobel • Chen, Kartik and Sobel (2008) • Impose additional restriction on CS equilibrium • No Incentive to Separate (NITS) • Only most informative equilibrium satisfies condition

  8. Related Literature: Costly Communication • Austen-Smith and Banks (2000) • Kartik (2007) • Add availability of costly messages to CS • Expand set of equilibria • Dewatripont and Tirole (2005) • Austen-Smith (1994) • Information understood or not

  9. Related Literature: Costly Communication • Cremer, Garicano and Prat (2007) • Finite number of partition elements • Sender and Receiver with aligned preferences • Optimal allocation into partitions • To coordinate

  10. Model • State of the world: s • uniformly distributed on [0,1] • exact value known by sender • unknown to receiver • Receiver to take action: a • on real numbers • Receiver's Payoffs: uR(a,s)=-(a-s)2

  11. Message Space • Sender can send messages • Message space: M ={m0,m1,m2,…} • Cost of messages • Message mi costs: c(i) • if i>j>0 • c(i)>c(j)>c(0)=0 • c(i)-c(i-1)>0 • Sender’s Payoffs: uS(a,s)=-(a-s-b)2-c(i) where b0

  12. Strategies • Sender’s Strategy: :[0,1]M • Receiver’s Strategy: : M R

  13. Model: Equilibrium Conditions • Equilibrium (*, *) require: • Receiver selects optimal action given message • Sender sends optimal message • Beliefs are derived from Bayes’ Rule whenever possible

  14. Necessary Conditions • h interval on which the hth message is sent • mh= *(s) for s[sh,sh+1) • Two relatively obvious necessary conditions: • 1+2+…+n=1 • where h0 for every h{1,…,n}

  15. Another Necessary Condition • h interval on which the hth message is sent • i interval size with message mi • Lemma 1: Necessary condition for equilibrium (h+1j)2–(hi)2 =4[c(i)-c(j)]+4b(h+1j+hi) • Messages associated with higher states • Are sent on larger intervals • Same as Crawford and Sobel (1982) • More costly signals are conserved • Are sent on smaller intervals

  16. Another Necessary Condition • Lemma 1: Necessary condition for equilibrium (h+1j)2–(hi)2 =4[c(i)-c(j)]+4b(h+1j+hi) • c=0 and b>0 • Costless communication, imperfect alignment • Reduces to (21) in Crawford and Sobel (1982) • c>0 and b=0 • Costly communication, perfect alignment • Order of intervals does not matter • Costly signals are conserved

  17. Equilibrium Characterization • What can we say without any restrictions of out-of-equilibrium beliefs? • Lemma 2: If c>0, then for any equilibrium • cheapest message (m0) will be transmitted for some states • and • will exist a completely uninformative equilibrium • cheapest message (m0) will be transmitted on all states

  18. Definition of Feasible • A (, ) is feasible if • satisfies necessary conditions • empty message is transmitted for some states

  19. Equilibrium • Proposition 1: All (, ) which are feasible • Can form an equilibrium • There are many, many equilibria • Like Crawford and Sobel

  20. c(i)=0.01(i) b=0 Eq. without “holes” Example Also, all permutations 0 1 1 m0 1 2 m0 m1 0.52 0.48 3 m0 m1 m2 0.271 0.392 0.337 4 m0 m1 m2 m3 0.336 0.302 0.227 0.108 No equilibrium with more than 4 messages

  21. c(i)=0.01(i) b=0 Eq. with “holes” Example Also, all permutations 0 1 m0 m1 0.52 0.48 m0 m2 0.46 0.54 m0 m3 2 0.56 0.44 . . . m0 m24 0.98 0.02 Many such equilibria involving 3 messages

  22. Restrict out-of-equilibrium beliefs • Which equilibria are admitted • if we restrict out-of-equilibrium beliefs? • No incentive to separate (NITS) • If observe out-of-equilibrium message • Receiver believes s=0

  23. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0

  24. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0 m0

  25. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0 m0 m1

  26. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0 m0 m1 m2

  27. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0 m0 m1 m2

  28. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0 m0 m1 m2

  29. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0.01

  30. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0.01 m0

  31. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0.01 m0 m1

  32. s uS c(i)=0.02i b=0.01 And similarly for c=0 m0 m1 m2

  33. s uS c=0 b=0.01

  34. The Reasonableness of NITS • Is NITS reasonable? • Is NITS more reasonable when b=0?

  35. NITS Discussion • Chen, Kartik, and Sobel (2008) apply NITS • uniform-quadratic case Crawford Sobel (1982) • only equilibrium with maximum partitions • Our specification is not identical

  36. Perfect Alignment of Preferences (b=0) • Things work pretty well • if b=0, c>0 • Condition NITS, picks out • “best” possible equilibria

  37. Results: No Holes • Lemma 3: Consider equilibrium with mi • Under Condition NITS, • if b=0 then every mj where ji • is also used in equilibrium • Intuition: Will not use a more costly signal • when a less costly one is unused

  38. Definition: NITS-Feasible • An (, ) is NITS-feasible if • satisfies necessary conditions • Lemma 3 is satisfied (“No Holes”)

  39. Maximal, NITS-feasible • By “No Holes” result • can characterize NITS-feasible (k, k) • by the most costly message mk • We will say that (k, k) maximal, NITS-feasible if • does not exist NITS-feasible (k’, k’) for k’>k • Lemma 4: If b=0 and c>0 there always exists • maximal, NITS-feasible (, )

  40. Existence and Uniqueness • Proposition 2: If b=0 • then under Condition NITS, • an equilibrium always exists • and it is exclusively • the maximal, NITS-feasible class

  41. Discussion: Existence and Uniqueness • Condition NITS • b=0 and c>0, uniform-quadratic • Unique: only most informative equilibria • Analogous to NITS • Chen, Kartik and Sobel (2008)) applied to original cheap talk model • b>0 and c=0, uniform-quadratic • Unique: only most informative equilibrium • When b>0 and c>0 • Not guaranteed uniqueness

  42. Only maximal, NITS-feasible Example c(i)=0.01(i) b=0 NITS 0 1 1 Not admitted m0 2 m0 Not admitted m1 3 Not admitted m0 m1 m2 4 m0 m1 m2 m3 No admissible equilibrium 5 or more messages

  43. Suppose that b=0.245 c(i)=0.01*i Equilibrium with single message m0 on [0,1] Equilibrium with two messages m0 on [0,0.03) m1 on [0.03,1] Example: Nonuniqueness when b>0

  44. Nonuniqueness Intuition • Q: Why does uniqueness fail for • b>0 and c>0? • For b>0 and c=0 • Intervals increasing along state space • For b=0 and c>0 • Intervals exclusively determined by costs • But when b>0 and c>0 • These effects interact • Can cause nonuniqueness

  45. Suppose that b=0.2 c(i)=0.01*i Two equilibria m1 on [0,0.08) m0 on [0.08,1] And m0 on [0,0.12) m1 on [0.12,1] Now suppose that c(i)=0.02*i One of two equilibria m0 on [0,0.14) m1 on [0.14,1] Better communication here! outperforms Goltsman et al. (2009) JET upper bound for receiver’s payoffs Example: Communication Costs

  46. Intuition 0 1 m1  • Intervals on higher numbers • larger • Intervals involving costly signals • smaller 0.06 0.94  m1 0.14 0.86

  47. Conclusion • Communication game: • Communication costs increasing • in complexity of message sent • Shades of understanding • When b=0, Condition NITS • unique class of equilibria with most messages

  48. Alternate Specifications of Communication • Q: Why not specify communication costs • which are decreasing in the size of interval? • A1: Pooling equilibrium seems more natural • Not a unique word for every object • A2: Some noise is helpful to communication • Blume, Board and Kawamura (2007) • A3: Must assume that receiver is • not sophisticated

  49. Setup: Communication seems to work this way Reality complex and nuanced Communication discrete and costly Natural way to vary cost of communication Results: “Some” communication when preferences are aligned (b=0) shades of understanding Pooling equilibrium When b>0 and c>0 Can outperform Goltsman et al. (2009) bound “So Why Should I Care?”

  50. Experimental • Experiments in communication games • Cai and Wang (2006) • Kawagoe and Takizawa (2009) • Test with simplified model

More Related