1 / 20

Inference in First Order Logic

Inference in First Order Logic. CS 171/271 (Chapter 9) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material. Inference Algorithms. Reduction to Propositional Inference Lifting and Unification Chaining Resolution. Propositionalization.

Download Presentation

Inference in First Order Logic

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Inference in First Order Logic CS 171/271 (Chapter 9) Some text and images in these slides were drawn fromRussel & Norvig’s published material

  2. Inference Algorithms • Reduction to Propositional Inference • Lifting and Unification • Chaining • Resolution

  3. Propositionalization • Strategy: convert KB to propositional logic and then use PL inference • Ground atomic sentences become propositional symbols • What about the quantifiers?

  4. Example • KB in FOL: • x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) • King(John) • Greedy(John) • Brother(Richard,John) • The last 3 sentences can be symbols in PL • Apply Universal Instantiation to the first sentence

  5. Universal Instantiation • UI says that from a universally quantified sentence, we can infer any sentence obtained by substituting a ground term for the variable • Back to Example • From: x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) • To: • King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) • King(Richard)  Greedy(Richard)  Evil(Richard) • …

  6. Issue with UI • Ground terms: all symbols that refer to objects as well as function applications (recall that function applications return objects) • For example, suppose Father is a function: • Father(John) and Father(Richard) are also objects/ground terms • But so are Father(Father(John)) and Father(Father(Father(John))) • Infinitely many ground terms/instantiations

  7. Existential Instantiation • Whenever there is a sentence, x P, introduce a new object symbol called the skolem constant and then add the unquantified sentence P, substituting the variable with that constant • Example: • From: x Crown(x)  OnHead(x, John) • To: Crown(Cnew)  OnHead(Cnew, John)

  8. Substitution • UI and EI apply substitutions • A substitution is represented by a variable v and a ground term g; {v/g} • Can have sets of these pairs if there are more variables involved • Let  be a sentence (possibly containing v) • SUBST( {v/g},  ) stands for the sentence that applies the substitution to 

  9. UI and EI Defined • UI:vα ___for any ground term gSUBST({v/g}, α) • EI:vα ___for some constant symbol k notSUBST({v/k}, α) yet in the knowledge base

  10. Back to Propositionalization • Given a KB in FOL, convert KB to PL by • applying UI and EI to quantified sentences • converting atomic sentences to symbols • If there are no functions (Datalog KB), UI application does not result in infinitely many sentences • Regular PL Inference can now be carried out without problems • What if there are functions?

  11. Dealing with Infinitely Many Ground Terms • Can set a depth-limit for ground terms • Depth specifies levels of function nesting allowed • Carry out reduction and inference process for depth 1, then 2, then 3, … • Stop when entailment can be concluded • This works if there is such a proof, but goes into an endless loop if there is not • The strategy is complete • The entailment problem in this sense is semidecidable

  12. Inefficiencies in Propositionalization • An inordinate number of irrelevant sentences may be generated, resulting from UI • This motivates generating only those sentences that are important in entailment

  13. Example • Suppose KB contains: • x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) • y Greedy(y) • King(John) • Suppose we want to conclude Evil(John) • Because of the existence of objects other than John (such as Richard) and the existence of functions, UI will generate many sentences

  14. Example, continued • It is sufficient to generate: • King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) • Greedy(John) • Which is just: • SUBST( {x/John}, King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) ) • SUBST( {y/John}, Greedy(y) ) • Applying the substitution matches the • Premises: King(x)  Greedy(x) • With other sentences in the KB:Greedy(y), King(John)

  15. Lifted Modus Ponens • Lifting: Raising propositional inference rules to first order logic • Example: Generalized Modus Ponens If there is a substitution θ, such thatSUBST(θ, pi) = SUBST(θ, pi’) for all i, then p1', p2', … , pn’, ( p1 p2 …  pn q) _______________________________________________________________________________ SUBST(θ,q) • In our example,  = {x/John, y/John}

  16. Unification • Process that makes logical expressions identical • Goal: match the premises of implications so that conclusions can be derived • UNIFY algorithm takes two sentences and returns a unifier (substitution) if it exists

  17. Unification Algorithm

  18. Unification Algorithm

  19. About UNIFY • UNIFY returns a Most General Unifier (MGU) • There are efficiency issues withOCCUR-CHECK function • May need to standardize apart: rename variables to avoid name clashes • Unification is a key component of all first-order algorithms

  20. What’s Next? • Forward and backward chaining algorithms for FOL that use unification • Resolution-based theorem proving systems

More Related