1 / 17

Theorem 3.5: Let f be an everywhere function from A to B. Then (i) f  I A = f .

Theorem 3.5: Let f be an everywhere function from A to B. Then (i) f  I A = f . (ii)I B  f = f . Proof. Concerning(i), let a  A, ( f  I A )(a) ?= f (a). Property (ii) is proved similarly to property (i).

effie
Download Presentation

Theorem 3.5: Let f be an everywhere function from A to B. Then (i) f  I A = f .

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Theorem 3.5: Let f be an everywhere function from A to B. Then • (i)f IA=f. • (ii)IB f = f. • Proof. Concerning(i), let aA, (f IA)(a) ?=f(a). • Property (ii) is proved similarly to property (i).

  2. Theorem 3.6: Let g be an everywhere function from A to B, and f be an everywhere function from B to C. Then • (1)if f and g are onto , then f g is also onto. • (2)If f and g are one to one, then f g is also one to one. • (3)If f and g are one-to-one correspondence, then f g is also one-to-one correspondence • Proof: (1)for every cC, there exists aA such that f g(a)=c

  3. (2)one to one:if ab,then f g(a)? f g(b) • (3)f and g are one-to-one correspondence, f and g are onto. By (1), f g are onto. • By (2),  f g are also one to one. Thus f g is also one-to-one correspondence.

  4. 2. Inverse functions • Inverse relation, • Function is a relation • Is the function’s inverse relation a function? No • Example: A={1,2,3},B={a,b}, f:A→B, f ={(1,a),(2,b),(3,b)} is a function, but inverse relation f -1={(a,1),(b,2),(b,3)} is not a function.

  5. Theorem 3.7: :(a) Let f be a function from A to B, Inverse relation f -1 is a function from B to A if only if f is one to one • (b) Let f be an everywhere function from A to B, Inverse relation f -1 is an everywhere function from B to A if only if f is one-to-one correspondence. • Proof: (a)(1)If f –1 is a function, then f is one to one • If there exist a1,a2A such that f(a1)=f(a2)=bB, then a1?=a2 • (2)If f is one to one,then f –1 is a function • f -1 is a function • For bB,If there exist a1,a2A such that (b,a1)f -1 and (b,a2) f -1,then a1?=a2

  6. Proof: (b)(1)If f –1 is an everywhere function, then f is one-to-one correspondence. • (i)f is onto. • For any bB,there exists aA such that f (a)=?b • (ii)f is one to one. • If there exist a1,a2A such that f (a1)=f (a2)=bB, then a1?=a2 • (2)If f is one-to-one correspondence,then f –1 is a everywhere function • f -1 is an everywhere function, for any bB,there exists one and only aA so that (b,a) f -1. • For any bB, there exists aA such that (b,a)?f -1. • For bB,If there exist a1,a2A such that (b,a1)f -1 and (b,a2) f -1,then a1?=a2

  7. Definition 3.5: Let f be one-to-one correspondence between A and B. We say that inverse relation f -1 is the everywhere inverse function of f. We denoted f -1:B→A. And if f (a)=b then f -1(b)=a. • Theorem 3.8: Let f be one-to-one correspondence between A and B. Then the inverse function f -1 is also one-to-one correspondence. • Proof: (1) f –1is onto (f –1 is a function from B to A • For any aA,there exists bB such that f -1(b)=a) • (2)f –1 is one to one • For any b1,b2B, if b1b2 then f -1(b1) f -1(b2). • If f:A→B is one-to-one correspondence, then f -1:B→A is also one-to-one correspondence. The function f is called invertible.

  8. Theorem 3.9: Let f be one-to-one correspondence between A and B. • Then • (1)(f -1)-1= f • (2)f -1 f=IA • (3)f  f -1=IB • Proof: (1)(f -1)-1= f • (2)f -1 f=IA • Let f:A→B and g:B→A, • Is g the inverse function of f ? • f g?=IB and g  f ?=IA

  9. Theorem 3.10:Let g be one-to-one correspondence between A and B, and f be one-to-one correspondence between B and C. Then (fg)-1= g-1f -1 • Proof: By Theorem 3.6, f g is one-to-one correspondence from A to C • Similarly, By theorem 3.7, 3.8, g-1 is a one-to-one correspondence function from B to A, and f –1 is a one-to-one correspondence function from C to B.

  10. Theorem 3.11: Let A and B be two finite set with |A|=|B|, and let f be an everywhere function from A to B. Then • (1)If f is one to one, then f is onto. • (2)If f is onto, then f is one to one. • The prove are left your exercises.

  11. 3.3 The Characteristic function of the set • function from universal set to {0,1} • Definition 3.6: Let U be the universal set, and let AU. The characteristic function of A is defined as a function from U to {0,1} by the following:

  12. Theorem 3.12: Let A and B be subsets of the universal set. Then, for any xU, we have • (1)A(x)0 if only if A= • (2)A(x)  1 if only if A=U; • (3)A(x)≦B(x) if only if AB; • (4)A(x) B(x) if only if A=B; • (5)A∩B(x)=A(x)B(x); • (6)A∪B(x)=A(x)+B(x)-A∩B(x);

  13. 3.4 Cardinality • Definition 3.7: The empty set is a finite set of cardinality 0. If there is a one-to-one correspondence between A and the set {0,1,2,3,…, n-1}, then A is a finite set of cardinality n. • Definition 3.8: A set A is countably infinite if there is a one-to-one correspondence between A and the set N of natural number. We write |A|=|N|=0. A set is countable if it is finite or countably infinite.

  14. Example: The set Z is countably infinite • Proof: f:N→Z,for any nN,

  15. The set Q of rational number is countably infinite, i.e. |Q|=|N|=0. • |[0,1]|0. • Theorem 3.13: The R of real numbers is not countably infinite. And |R|=|[0,1]|. • Theorem 3.14: The power set P(N) of the set N of natural number is not countably infinite. And |P(N)|=|R|=1. • Theorem 3.15(Cantor’s Theorem): For any set, the power set of X is cardinally larger than X. • N, P (N),P (P (N)),…

  16. 3.5 Paradox • 1.Russell’s paradox • AA,AA。 • Russell’s paradox: Let S={A|AA}. The question is, does SS? • i.e. SS or SS? • If SS, • If SS, • The statements " SS " and " SS " cannot both be true, thus the contradiction.

  17. Exercise: P176 21,22,32,33 • P181 4, • Prove Theorem 3.11 • Prove:(1)|(0,1)|=|R| (2)|[0,1]|=|R| • Next: • Pigeonhole principle P88 3.3 • Permutations of sets P79-81, 3.1

More Related