1 / 21

Philosophy of Emotion

Philosophy of Emotion.

dusty
Download Presentation

Philosophy of Emotion

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Philosophy of Emotion Contemporary analytic philosophy of emotions is currently dominated by two opposing camps. In one camp we have those generally labelled cognitivists and in the other those who favour a Jamesian approach, the neo-Jamesians. The‖term‖’cognitivism‛‖brings together writers on emotions, some of whom might be termed pure cognitivists: e.g. Solomon (1976 & 2003c), Taylor (1985) and Nussbaum (2004); and those who might be termed hybrid cognitivists: e.g. Goldie (2000) Greenspan (1993) Nash (1987) and Stocker (1987). Neo-Jamesianism, as the name suggests, brings together philosophers and psychologists who‖advance‖a‖contemporary‖variant‖of‖William‖James’s‖account‖of‖emotion and in doing so often align themselves with the research program initiated by Darwin ([1872] 1965) and later Ekman (1972); those Darwinian claims are often buttressed by theoretical claims drawn from neuroscience and cognate theories of mind: e.g. Damasio (1994), Prinz (2004) and Robinson (1995).

  2. Cognitivists and Jamesians In short, cognitivists take emotions to be centrally, and explain them in terms of, appraisals, judgements or evaluative beliefs; neo-Jamesians explain emotions in terms of awareness of bodily changes, usually patterned changes in the Autonomic Nervous System (ANS). How the debate is polarised can be captured by returning to a passage from William James’s paper in Mind, published in 1884, a passage frequently quoted and/or referred to by those on either side of the debate. Our natural way of thinking about … emotions is that the mental perception of some fact excites the mental affection called the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives rise to the bodily expression. My thesis on the contrary is that the bodily changes follow directly the PERCEPTION of the exciting fact, and that our feeling of the same changes as they occur IS the emotion. (James, 1884: 190-191. Emphasis in original)

  3. Cognitivism and Jamesianism The cognitivist philosophers of emotion favour analysis of the thoughts that constitute the emotion, in its social situation or embedded in a narrative: the‖’natural‖way‖of‖thinking‖about‖…‖emotions’,‖as‖James‖puts‖it. Neo-Jamesians, in following James’s‖claim‖that‖the ‘bodily changes follow directly the PERCEPTION of the exciting fact’‖reject‖the talk of thoughts and favour a cognitive neuroscience approach, sometimes drawing on or appealing to evolutionary psychology/socio-biology.

  4. Cognitivism and Jamesianism • So, cognitivists depict emotional episodes as fundamentally outward-facing and Jamesians as fundamentally introspective. • Cognitivists argue that emotions are rational; Jamesians argue that they are non-rational or rationally inert irruptions in an otherwise rational life (though recently neo-Jamesians have sought to give and account of emotions which can accommodate the rationality of emotion while retaining the central Jamesian commitment, e.g. Prinz). • In cognitive theories, intentionality is at centre stage, our thoughts are directed at something in the world; in neo-Jamesian theories, passivity is at centre stage, we are struck by or afflicted by something.

  5. Deigh’s Emotion Gap John Deigh (2004) has identified that the problem facing theories of emotions in both camps is their inability to cover both of two facts about emotions. Fact one is the intentionality of emotion. Fact two is that, as Deigh puts it, ‘emotions are common to both humans and beasts’ (with caveats that a. humans have a broader set of emotions, and b. we are not committed to all beasts having emotions). Whenever theorists of emotion try to cover intentionality adequately, they do so, according to Deigh, by forgoing the ability to explain emotion in non-human animals. Of course, cognitivists are historically seen as strong on fact one, while Jamesians/Darwinians are taken to be strong on fact two. We might equally observe that it is often taken to be the case that cognitivists face substantial difficulty in acknowledging fact two just as Jamesians, at least appear to, deny fact one.

  6. A successful theory of emotions must account for both of these facts [Facts one and two]. It cannot skirt them. Yet accounting for both has proven to be surprisingly difficult. Some theories, particularly the cognitivist theories that have been so influential in philosophy and psychology over the last thirty years, use the first fact as their point of departure and leading idea, but they then have trouble accommodating the second. Other theories, particularly those that have developed under the‖influence‖of‖Darwin’s‖seminal‖work‖The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (1998), take the second fact as their springboard, but then they have trouble accommodating the first. The reason in either case, is the way intentional states of mind are typically understood and the way primitive emotions are typically understood. The problem of closing this gap seems to outstrip the resources of these theories. The point is not generally recognised, however. It tends to‖lie‖beyond‖the‖theories’‖horizons. (Deigh, 2004: p. 10)

  7. PAUL‖GRIFFITHS:‖THE‖ELIMINATIVIST’S‖RESPONSE Paul Griffiths (1997) has suggested that the problem is the very thought that one can, indeed, provide an account of emotion. For Griffiths, the term “emotion” does not pick out a natural kind, but rather two natural kinds (plus, possibly, one pseudo-kind of “disclaimed action ‘emotions’”). The vernacular concept ‘emotion’, should be eliminated, according to Griffiths, in favour of two new kind terms.‖

  8. Two Natural Kinds The first kind of emotions are the “basic emotions”, best explained, according to Griffiths, by Ekman’s “Affect Program research” and complemented by the work of Damasio. These basic emotions are said to roughly correspond to the vernacular emotion concepts of “anger, surprise, joy, and disgust” The second kind of emotions are the “higher cognitive” or “complex” emotions, best explained, according to Griffiths, by evolutionary psychological explanation. These “complex” emotions are said to correspond roughly to the vernacular emotion concepts of “guilt, remorse, loyalty, and shame.”

  9. Analogue / Homologue Distinction Griffiths’ response to the problem as identified by Deigh, therefore, is to simply say that providing one theory that covers both facts cannot be done; thus, trying to provide one is ill-conceived. Any‖likeness‖between‖the‖’basic’‖emotionsand‖the ’complex’‖emotions is purely analogous. Griffiths imports here a distinction from the philosophy of biology between analogous correspondence and homologous correspondence: the former is merely superficial likeness (a likeness in function or purpose), claims Griffiths. While the latter, homologous correspondence, is real correspondence (a correspondence in essential structural form).

  10. Blade Runner • Let us imagine two beings who appear to share the same attributes. They look like two healthy human beings. They both feel pain, though one has a higher pain threshold than the other. • They respond to loss and bereavement in the same way, though one has experienced much and is now more ‘hardened.’ • they understand each other as on occasion being afraid and on having lost a loved one, being grief-stricken. One comforts the other and reports their grief in a certain tone of voice to friends and relatives. • In‖this‖way‖they‖acknowledge‖one‖another,‖through acknowledgement of‖one‖another’s fears, grief, joy &c. . • All things considered, they are the same sort of being in terms of their lives in the world, their interactions and transactions with others in their shared world. • What changes for you about this story if one finds that one of these two beings has radically different biological mechanisms that physically facilitate certain of their typical fear behaviour or grief behaviour?

  11. Prinz and the Emotion Problem So we have a serious puzzle. The fact that emotions are meaningful, reason sensitive, and intentional suggests that they must be cognitive. The fact that some emotions arise without intervention of the neocortex suggests that emotions cannot all be cognitive. The emotions that arise in this way seem to be meaningful. This seems to suggest that being meaningful does not require being cognitive. Noncognitive states are explanatorily anaemic and cognitive states are explanatorily superfluous. Noncognitive theories give us too little, and cognitive theories give us too much. Call this the Emotion Problem. (Prinz 2003a: 78)

  12. Prinz’sEmotion Problem as a syllogism • Cognition is absent. [put Prinz’s‖way: nothing is taking place in the brain which involves the intervention of the neocortex] • (while‖‘cognition’‖is‖absent),‖the‖person‖is‖in‖an‖emotional state and‖this‖suggeststhat something akin to cognition—something that fulfils the outward criteria for being cognition—is taking place. [i.e. something akin to the perception and evaluation of an object] • the conclusion drawn is that something else, other than the involvement of the neocortex, must be playing the role of cognition; something noncognitive must give-forth meaning, and must be directed onto things in the world: must be intentional. [Since cognition-as-neural-activity-involving-the-intervention-of-the-neocortex (what Prinz takes to be cognition) is not present, but a meaningful emotional episode is, meaning must emerge from an embodied emotion having semantic properties which enable it to refer in the absence of cognition (in the absence of neocortical intervention).]

  13. Prinz’s ‘solution’ to his ‘problem’ Emotions‖can‖be‖individuated‖by‖their‖reliable‖elicitors.‖This suggestion‖canbe taken a step further. According to prevailing theories of mental representation, a mental state gets its intentional content in virtue of being reliably caused (or having the function of being reliably caused) by something (Dretske, 1981, 1988;‖Fodor‖1990). Let’s assume that‖a‖theory‖of‖this‖kind,‖whatever the details, is correct.[11] There is some causal relation that confers content. If emotions are perceptions of bodily states, they are caused by changes in the body. But if those changes in the body are reliably caused by core relational themes, then our representations of the body may also represent those themes. (Prinz, 2004: 55)

  14. Responding to Prinz We‖are‖told‖by‖Prinz‖that‖cognition‖does not take place because the neocortex does not intervene in the brain processes; hence, we cannot make sense of our emotions having meaning when they occur in the absence of neocortical intervention. The solution is proposed that we have some inner concepts; i.e. the semantically endowed inner concepts of psychosemantics. But if our ordinary (public) concepts were not sufficient for meaning in the absence of neocortical intervention then why are the concepts of psychosemantics? What is the telling difference between our public concepts and those of psychosemantics? The only difference seems to be that the former are outer and public, and the latter are, in some sense, inner and private; this seems far from sufficient for the latter to have any powers over and above those we might predicate of the former.

  15. World-Taking Cognitivism when one sees an event as (for example) shameful, one has perceived an internal relation between one’s way of taking (seeing) that event—i.e., one’s conceptual characterization of it—and one’s conception of shame. Such internal relations can emerge as live for us through the forming of both our human and second nature (Bildung). In those situations where we might not be alive to such aspects at a particular time, we might come to be so at a later time by means of the dawning of an aspect

  16. Léopard’s shame “Some try to show remorse but tremble before the truth. They sneak around it, because of too many conflicting interests, and wind up flung backwards. It was in a camp in Congo that I first felt my heart ache. I prayed, hoping to find relief, but in vain. After prayers or hymns, shame waited for me, without fail. So I began being sorry out loud, paying no attention to the mockery spewing from my comrades’ mouths. In prison I told my whole truth. It came out freely. Ever since then, whenever someone asks me for it, it flows the same way.”

  17. Shame and Humanity In the perpetration of his crimes, Léopard refused to acknowledge the humanity of his victims. It was not that he refused to admit that the extension of the concept of “human being” is “member of the species Homo sapiens.” It was rather that he had refused to acknowledge, had turned away from, the meaning of human being as a moral concept with, we might say, all its normative richness. He had gone through a process whereby he failed to acknowledge the humanity of others—that is to say, he failed to see the moral claims acknowledging the humanity that another make’s on one. Léopard was in a state of denial regarding the humanity of those he subjected to brutality, suffering, and death, and in being so, in being able to act as he did, he had also denied that humanity to himself. This is what creeps up on Léopard; the situations in which Léopard committed those crimes had not elicited shame because he had not seen the acts as shameful. In carrying out those actions, Léopard denied—was in denial as regards—the humanity of his victims and had justified the suspending of the pre-genocide order, whereby acting in such a way is inhuman.

  18. Shame and Humanity One helpful way to understand Léopard’s ability to commit his crimes without, until years later, feeling remorse or shame is to think of it in terms of the internal relations that under normal conditions hold between the moral concept of human being and concepts such as dignity, care, compassion, and justice, and those relations being suspended, or (it may be more accurate to say) having been latent in Léopard’s case for some time. When those relations were re-established, when they came to life, then shame for his acts emerged.

  19. Four Types of Shame-Absence • Kaspar Hauser type • Absence of enculturation (passive) • Diogenes of Synope type • Active denial of the culturally-conferred judgements • World-Change type • A radical change in social norms, rendering one’s enculturation at odds with one’s lifeworld • Object Prejudice type • The object of the emotion is diffuse and complex and thus can seem absent (leading the emotion to be absent)

More Related