1 / 30

General Resolution method in FOL

General Resolution method in FOL. Lesson 8. Typical problems to solve. Proving logical validity of a formula: Formula F is logically valid , denoted |= F , iff F is true in all interpretations, i.e., every interpretation structure is its model Proving the validity of an argument:

clement
Download Presentation

General Resolution method in FOL

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. General Resolution method in FOL Lesson 8 General resolution Method

  2. Typical problems to solve • Proving logical validity of a formula: • Formula F is logically valid, denoted |= F, iff F is true in all interpretations, i.e., every interpretation structure is its model • Proving the validity of an argument: • An argument is valid, denoted P1, …, Pn |= Q, iff the formula Q is true in all the models of the set of assumptions P1, …, Pn • What follows from the assumptions? • P1, …, Pn |= ? General resolution Method

  3. Typical problems, tasks • Their solution by examining the infinite set of models is difficult; it is not possible to automatize semantic proofs • Therefore we look for syntactic (mechanic) methods of proving • One of them is the method of semantic tableau based on the transformation of a formula into its disjunctive normal form (disadvantage:we often need to perform many transformations using the distributive laws) • Now we are going to learn a very effective method that is used also for automatic theorem proving and programming in logic: the resolution method for FOL(generalization of the resolution method for propositional logic) • Rezolution methodmakes use of the conjunctive normal form of a formula General resolution Method

  4. Resolution method • It is applicable to a formula in the special kind of the conjunctive normal form: Skolem clausal form • It makes use of the indirect proof • It serves as a theoretical foundation for automatic theorem proving and logic programming; • In particular for the programming language PROLOG General resolution Method

  5. Resolution method In order to generalize the resolution method of propositional logic, there are two problems: • Transformation into the Skolem clausal form: x1…xn [C1  …  Cm]where Ci are clauses, i.e., disjunctions of literals, e.g.: P(x)  Q(f(x,y)) • In order to apply the resolution rule on a pair of a positive and negative literals, the literals have to be identical; we have to unifythem. For instance: P(x)  Q(f(x),y)P(g(y))  Q(x,z) The literals P(x), P(g(y)) might have been eliminated, if they were identical; we have to unify them by substituting g(y) for x. General resolution Method

  6. Transformation into the clausal form (Skolem) • Existential generalization (if there are free varaibles, then bind them by  (consistency preserving) • Elimination of dispensable quantifiers • Elimination of the connectives ,  • Moving negation inside (applying de Morgan laws) • Renaming variables • Moving quantifiers to the right • Elimination of existential quantifiers(Skolemization – consistency preserving) • Moving general quantifiers to the left • Applying distributive laws General resolution Method

  7. Resolution method – example. |= [x y P(x,y) yz Q(y,z)]x yz [P(x,y)  Q(y,z)] 1. Negating the formula and variables renaming: [x y’P(x,y’) yz Q(y,z)]uvw [P(u,v) Q(v,w)] 2. Elimination of existential quantifiers. MIND ! [x P(x,f(x)) yQ(y,g(y))]vw [P(a,v) Q(v,w)] 3. Moving the quantifiers to the left: x yvw [P(x,f(x))  Q(y, g(y))[P(a,v) Q(v,w)]] 4. The formula is obviously not satisfiable;how to prove it? 5. Write down the clauses and perform the unification of literals, i.e., substitute appropriate terms for variables, so that to be able to apply the resolution rule: General resolution Method

  8. Resolution method – example • P(x,f(x)) • Q(y,g(y)) • P(a,v) Q(v,w) • Now we have to apply resolution rule. In order to resolve clauses 1. and 3., we have to substitute the term afor the variable x andthe term f(a) for variable v. • Q(f(a),w) resolving 1., 3., substitution:x/a, v/f(a) • resolving 2., 4., substitution:y/f(a), w/g(f(a)) QED – the negated formula is a contradiction, which means that the original formula is logically valid Note: When unifying the literals, it is necessary to substitute for all the occurrences of a variable! General resolution Method

  9. Skolem clausal form Literal: atomic formula or the negation of an atomic formula.Examples: P(x, g(y)), Q(z) Clause: disjunction of literals, e.g.: P(x, g(y)) Q(z) Skolem clausal form: x1…xn [C1 … Cm], a closed formula, where Ci are clauses, disjunctions of literals, e.g.: P(x)  Q(f(x,y)) Skolemization (elimination of existential quantifiers): x y1...yn A(x, y1,...,yn)  y1...yn A(c, y1,...,yn) where c is anew, in the language not used constant y1...ynx A(x, y1,...,yn)  y1...yn A(f(y1,...,yn), y1,...,yn) where f is anew, in the language not used functional symbol General resolution Method

  10. Skolemization is consistency preserving y1...ynxA(x, y1,...,yn)  y1...ynA(f(y1,...,yn), y1,...,yn) BBS • Proof: Let the structure Ibe a model of the formula BS(Skolemised). Then for anyn-tuple of individuals i1, i2,…,init holds that (n+1)-tuple of individuals i1, i2,…,in, fU (i1, i2,…,in)  AU, wherefUis the function assigned to the symbol f (in the interpretation I) and AUis the relation defined by the formula Ain the interpretation I. Then the interpretation structure Iis also a model of the formula B = y1y2…ynx A(x, y1, y2,…,yn). • Hence every model of the formulaBS is a model of the formula B, but not vice versa, ieBS|= B. • The set of models MBSof the formula BSis a subset of the set of models MBof the formulaB: MBS  MB. • If MBS  (i.e., BS is satisfiable) then MB  , i.e., Bis satisfiable as well. • IfMB = , i.e.Bis not satisfiable, then MBS = , i.e.,BSis not satisfiable, which is sufficient for the indirect proof. General resolution Method

  11. Thoralf Albert SkolemBorn: 23 May 1887 in Sandsvaer, Buskerud, NorwayDied: 23 March 1963 in Oslo, Norway Skolem was remarkably productive publishing around 180 papers on topics such as Diophantine equations, mathematical logic, group theory, lattice theory and set theory General resolution Method

  12. Transformation into the Skolem clausal form A  AS: • Existential generalization (consistency preserving) • Elimination of dispensable quantifiers (that do not bind any variables – equivalent transformation) • Elimination of,  (applying the PL laws – equivalent transformation) • Moving negation inside (applying de Morgan laws – equivalent transformation) • Renaming variables (equivalent transformation) • Moving quantifiers to the right (equivalent transformation): Qx (A@B(x))  A@QxB(x), Qx (A(x)@B)  Qx A(x)@B, where@ is a conjunction or disjunction connective, Q is a quantifier (general or existential) • Elimination of existential quantifiers(Skolemize the subformulas QxB(x), QxA(x) obtain in the step 6) • Moving general quantifiers to the left (equivalent transformation) • Applying distributive laws (equivalent transformation) General resolution Method

  13. TransformingA AS(Skolem) • The resulting formulaASis not equivalent to the original formula A (nor does it follow from A), but it holds thatifAhas a model then AShas a model.It also holds that AS |= A, but the two formulas are not equivalent. • The non-equivalent steps are: • Existential generalisation • Skolemization (elimination of existential quantifiers) • This is the reason why the resolution method is used as an indirect proof. • It can be used for a direct proof only if the assumptions do not contain any existential quantifier General resolution Method

  14. Transformation: A  AS • Always follow the above Skolem algorithm (9 steps). Some of them can be omitted, but do not transform into the conjunctive normal form first, and then Skolemize (as you can sometimes read). In other words, do not omit the step 6. • Example: the importance of thestep 6 (quantifiers to the right – moved to the subformulas containing the quantified variables). • We will illustrate an erroneous practice of omitting the step 6 by (not)proving that |= x A(x) x A(x): • negating the formula: x A(x)  x A(x), • Renaming variables: x A(x)  y A(y), • Moving quantifiers to the left: • x [A(x)  y A(y)]  x y [A(x)  A(y)], and • Skolemize: x [A(x)  A(f(x))]. • But the terms x and f(x) cannot be unified! Thus we did not prove the above tautology, though the resolution method is a complete proof method. Each logically valid formula is provable: • |= A  | A • The problem consists in the fact that we Skolemized aftermoving quantifiers to the left. We have to do it before, when the quantifiers are to the right – at the subformulas that they actually quantify. General resolution Method

  15. Example: A  AS x {P(x)  z {y [Q(x,y)  P(f(x1))]  y [Q(x,y)  P(x)]}} 1.,2. Existential generalisation and elimination of z: x1 x {P(x)  {y [Q(x,y)  P(f(x1))]  y [Q(x,y)  P(x)]}} 3.,4. Renaming y, elimination of: x1 x {P(x)  {y [Q(x,y)  P(f(x1))] z[Q(x,z)  P(x)]}} 5.,6. Negation moved inside, quantifiers to the right: x1 x {P(x)  {[y Q(x,y)  P(f(x1))] [zQ(x,z)  P(x)]}} 7. Elimination of the existential quantifiers: x {P(x)  {[Q(x,g(x))  P(f(a))] [zQ(x,z)  P(x)]}} 8. Quantifier z moved to the left: x z {P(x)  {[Q(x,g(x))  P(f(a))] [Q(x,z)  P(x)]}} 9. Distributive law: x z {[P(x)  Q(x,g(x))]  [P(x) P(f(a))] [P(x) Q(x,z)  P(x)]} 10. simplifying: x {[P(x)  Q(x,g(x))]  [P(x) P(f(a))]} General resolution Method

  16. The way of proving by resolution • Proof of the logical validity of a formula A: • Negate the formula A • TransformAinto the clausal Skolem form (A)S • Step-by-step apply the resolution rule (via unifying the literals) and try to prove that the formula (A)S is not satisfiable, hence also the formula A does not have a model, which means that A is logically valid. • Proof of the validity of an argumentP1,…,Pn|Z • Negate Z • Transform the assumptions and the negated conclusion into the Skolem clausal form • Step-by-step apply the resolution rule (via unifying the literals) and try to prove the inconsistency of theset {P1,…,Pn, Z} General resolution Method

  17. Unification of literals • Example: • xyzv[P(x, f(x)) Q(y, h(y))  (P(a, z)  Q(z, v))] • How to prove that the formula does not have a model? 1. P(x, f(x)) 2. Q(y, h(y)) 3. P(a, z)  Q(z, v) Now if we want to resolve the respective clauses; but there are no identical terms in the respective pairs of literals. However, all the variables are bound by the general quantifier. Hence we can apply the law of specialization, and thus substitute terms for variables in order to find the witness of inconsistency: In order to unify literals of 1 and 3, we use the substitution x/a, z/f(a). General resolution Method

  18. Unification of literals After substituting we obtain the following clauses: 1’. P(a, f(a)) 2. Q(y, h(y)) 3‘. P(a, f(a))  Q(f(a), v) • Now resolving 1‘ and 3‘ we obtain: 4. Q(f(a), v) • Now in order to resolve 2. and 4., we again use a substitution: y/f(a), v/h(f(a)) • and get 2‘. Q(f(a), h(f(a)) ) 4’.Q(f(a), h(f(a)) ) 5. • By resolving 2’, 4’we obtain an empty clause that does not have a model. Hence the original formula A does not have a model, it is a contradiction. General resolution Method

  19. Unification of literals Up to now we sought particular substitutions in order to unify literalsad hoc, intuitively looking for opposite “similar” literals We need to find an algorithm of unification. There are many such algorithms, we will examine two of them: • Herbrand procedure • Robinson unification algorithm Ad (a) A formula F is not satisfiable iff it is not true in any interpretation structure, over any universe of discourse. It might be useful to find just one universe such that F is a contradiction iff F is not satisfiable over any interpretation structure over this universe. Is there any such universe? Yes, it was discovered by Herbrand, and it is called Herbrand’s universe. General resolution Method

  20. Jacques HerbrandBorn: 12 Feb 1908 in Paris, FranceDied: 27 July 1931 in La Bérarde, Isère, France École Normale Supérieure at the age of 17 (!) His doctoral thesis was approved in April 1929 On a holiday in the Alps he died in a mountaineering accident at the age of 23 General resolution Method

  21. Herbrand procedure Herbranduniverse HF: consists of all the possible terms made up from the constants and functional symbols occurring in the formula; if there is no constant in the formula, then use any constant. Example: • For the formula A = x [P(a) Q(b) P(f(x))]the HA = {a, b, f(a), f(b), f(f(a)), f(f(b)), …} • For the formula B = x y P( (f(x), y, g(x,y) )the HB = {a, f(a), g(a,a), f(f(a)), g(a,f(a)), g(f(a),a), …} Basic instances of a clause: all the variables are substituted for by the elements of Herbrand universe Theorem (Herbrand): A formulaAin the Skolem clausal form is not satisfiable iff there is a finite conjunction of its basic instances that is not satisfiable. General resolution Method

  22. Herbrand procedure Example: 1. P(x, f(x)) 2. Q(y, h(y)) 3. P(a, z)  Q(z, v) • Here the HA = {a, f(a), h(a), f(f(a)), f(h(a)), h(f(a)), h(h(a)), …}. Now we create basic instances, substituting elements of (the ordered) Herbrand universe for variables: Substitution1: {x/a, y/a,z/a, v/a} • P(a, f(a))  Q(a, h(a)) [P(a, a)  Q(a, a)] Substitution2: {x/a, y/a,z/a, v/f(a)} • P(a, f(a))  Q(a, h(a)) [P(a, a)  Q(a, f(a))] etc., till we find Substitutionn: {x/a, y/f(a),z/f(a), v/h(f(a))} • P(a,f(a))  Q(f(a),h(f(a))) [P(a,f(a))  Q(f(a),h(f(a)))] Contradiction General resolution Method

  23. Herbrand Procedure Herbrand procedure is a method that partially decides whether a given formula F is a contradiction; if F is a contradiction then Herbrand procedure answers YES after a finite number of steps, otherwise it may not answer at all. (One of the corollaries of Gödel’s theorem; there is no procedure that would decide it totally.) Problem: Space and time complexity of the algorithm; the number of basic instances we need to generate till we find the witness of contradiction is often to large to be computationally tractable. General resolution Method

  24. John Alan Robinson • In his 1965 article "A Machine-Oriented Logic Based on the Resolution Principle" John Alan Robinson laid an important foundation for a whole branch of automated deduction systems. The original Prolog is essentially a refined automated theorem prover based on Robinson's resolution General resolution Method

  25. Robinson’s algorithm (1965) • Let A be a formula containing variables xi, i=1,2,...,n. Let us denote  ={x1/t1, x2/t2,...,xn/tn} the simultaneous substitution of terms ti for all the occurrences of variables xi for i=1,2,...,n. Then let Abe the formula that arises from A by performing the substitution . • Unification (unification substitution) of formulas A, B is the substitution  such that A = B. • The general unification of formulas A, B is the unification  such that any other unification  of formulas A, B it holds that  =  (where , it is not an empty substitution); in other words, the general unification leaves as much as possible variables free. General resolution Method

  26. Robinson’s algorithm (1965) It is the algorithm of finding the general unification: • Assume that A = P(t1, t2,...,tn), B = P(s1,s2,...,sn), where (for the sake of simplicity) at least one of the terms ti, siis a variable. 1. For i = 1,2,...,ndo: • Ifti = sithen i =  (the empty substitution). • If ti sithen check whether the terms ti, siare such that one of them is a variable, say x, and the other term, say r, does not contain this variable x. • If Yes, then i = {x/r}. • If No, then finish the cycle: the formulas A, B are not unifiable. 2. If the cycle were not finished by the exception ad (d), then A, B are unifiable, and the general unification  = 12...n(the composed substitution). General resolution Method

  27. Robinson’s algorithm Example: A = Px, f(x), u, B = Py, z, g(x,y) • 1 = {x/y}, A1 = P(y, f(y), u, B1 = Py, z, g(y,y) • 2 = {z/f(y)}, A12 = P(y, f(y), u, B12 = Py, f(y), g(y,y) • 3 = {u/g(y,y)}, A123 = P(y, f(y), g(y,y), B123 = Py, f(y), g(y,y). • The composed substitution=123is the general unification of the formulas A, B: {x/y, z/f(y), u/g(y,y)} General resolution Method

  28. General resolution rule A  L1, B  L2  A B where  is the general unification of L1, L2: L1 = L2 General resolution Method

  29. Example: prove the logical validity of xy [{P(x,y) Q(x, f(g(x)))} {R(x) x Q(x, f(g(x)))}xR(x)] xP(x, g(x)) 1. Negate the formula: xy [{P(x,y) Q(x, f(g(x)))} {R(x) x Q(x, f(g(x)))}xR(x)]  x P(x, g(x)) 2. Eliminate existential quantifiers, and rename the variables: xy [{P(x,y) Q(x, f(g(x)))} {R(x) Q(a, f(g(a)))}R(b)]  z P(z, g(z)) 3. Write down the clauses (after eliminating the implication): General resolution Method

  30. Example xy [{P(x,y) Q(x, f(g(x)))} {R(x) Q(a, f(g(a)))}R(b)] z P(z, g(z)) • P(x,y) Q(x, f(g(x))) • R(x) Q(a, f(g(a))) • R(b) • P(z, g(z)) • Q(x, f(g(x))) 1, 4: z/x, y/g(x) • Q(a, f(g(a))) 2, 3: x/b • 5, 6: x/a Note: Parent clauses to resolve are chosen in such a way that leaves as much as possible variables free (for further substitutions) General resolution Method

More Related