1 / 24

Fair burden sharing: The possible role of the Greenhouse Development Rights Framework

Fair burden sharing: The possible role of the Greenhouse Development Rights Framework. Dr. Paul Baer Assistant Professor School of Public Policy Georgia Institute of Technology Co-founder, EcoEquity. Australia National University, Canberra 1 July, 2011.

chung
Download Presentation

Fair burden sharing: The possible role of the Greenhouse Development Rights Framework

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Fair burden sharing:The possible role of the Greenhouse Development Rights Framework Dr. Paul Baer Assistant Professor School of Public Policy Georgia Institute of Technology Co-founder, EcoEquity Australia National University, Canberra 1 July, 2011

  2. The Greenhouse Development Rights Framework Authors Paul Baer (EcoEquity) Tom Athansiou (EcoEquity) SivanKartha (Stockholm Environment Institute) Eric Kemp-Benedict (SEI) Key Supporters have included Christian Aid (UK) Oxfam (International) European APRODEV Network The Heinrich Böll Foundation (Germany) MISTRA Foundation CLIPORE Programme (Sweden) Stockholm Environment Institute (International) Rockefeller Brothers Fund (USA) Town Creek Foundation (USA) www.GreenhouseDevelopmentRights.org

  3. GDRs: roots • Authors were originally supporters of equal per capita allocations/contraction and convergence • Basis of founding of EcoEquity in 2000, book “Dead Heat” • Following the CAN “Bali Equity Summit” in 2002, we tried to develop “per capita plus” – per capita modified to take account of national circumstances • This turned out to be impractical, so we returned to the “right to development” • First presented in 2004, reached maturity with publication of first edition in 2007

  4. The climate challenge: in three steps Global 2ºc pathway Emissions pathway in the developing world Emissions pathway in the industrialized world

  5. Per capita emissions allocated according to “contraction and convergence” (2030 convergence year) under an emissions pathway (based on Den Elzen et al. 2007) designed to stabilize atmospheric GHG concentrations at 450 ppm CO2-equivalent.

  6. Greenhouse Development Rights overview • A global climate policy framework for “burden sharing” • Assigns obligations to countries based on aggregating the wealth and GHG emissions of their citizens • “Capacity” (ability to pay) • and “responsibility” (contribution to the problem) • Combined “Responsibility and Capacity Indicator” (RCI) • Excludes from consideration the wealth and emissions of poor individuals, below a “development threshold” • Rich individuals are treated equally (have obligations) wherever they live • In principle, an individually-based “right to development”

  7. The ethical basis of GDRs • Based on cosmopolitan egalitarianism • Individuals not countries are bearers of rights and obligations (in theory) • Countries are treated as aggregates of individuals • Individuals treated the same regardless of where they are born • An idealist/constructivist account of politics and international relations • Ideas matter • Individual action matters • Countries act out of normative beliefs as well as self interest (and self-interest is subject to “construction”)

  8. Defining and measuring capacity • Capacity is a moral term: “resources that can be contributed without undue sacrifice” • This raises the classic question of the “efficiency” with which resources are converted to welfare • Historically captured by ideas of “basic needs”, luxuries, etc. • Makes sense at an individual level • Our definition: per capita income over $7500 “development threshold”

  9. Defining and measuring responsibility • Responsibility is an ambiguous term • Moral responsibility is not the same as causal responsibility • Collective (e.g., national) responsibility is problematic in many ways • Nonetheless, “polluter pays” and other versions of responsibility have strong support • Our definition: cumulative CO2 emissions from fossil fuels (and cement) since 1990

  10. Income and Capacity income distributions (relative to a “development threshold”)

  11. Emissions and Responsibility fossil CO2 (since 1990) (showing portion defined as “responsibility”)

  12. National obligations based on national “capacity” and “responsibility”

  13. National obligations (based on “responsibility” and “capacity”) over time

  14. Allocating global mitigation obligationsamong countries according to responsibility & capacity 14

  15. Implicationsfor United States US mitigation obligation amounts to a reduction target exceeding 100% after ~2025 (“negative emission allocation”). 15

  16. Implicationsfor United States • Here, physical domestic reductions (~25% below 1990 by 2020) are only part of the total US obligation. The rest would be met internationally. 16

  17. Implications for China 中国的测算结果 17

  18. Implications for China 中国的测算结果 A fraction of China's reduction, (and most of the reductions in the South) are driven by industrialized country reduction commitments. 18

  19. National Obligations in 2020 (for climate costs = 1% of GWP)

  20. Climate obligations, imagined as a (mildly progressive) tax Note that EC effort-sharing proposal imagines global mitigation costs of €175 billion, or about ¼% of the EC’s projected 2020 Gross World Product

  21. GDRs: Strengths • It is by some standards relatively simple • It is specific and complete: it can actually be used to produce numbers. • In theory it actually does protect the right to development - the necessary costs for each country are borne only by the “already developed” • Compared to resource sharing proposals, it actually addresses adaptation costs • By assigning obligations to rich people in poor countries, it answers a primary criticism of Annex-based proposals • It has been developed organically by a team that is closely integrated with both civil society networks (CAN) and academic and policy networks

  22. GDRs: Weaknesses • It is by some standards relatively complex • Even the numbers it produces are subject to a wide range of “uncertainties” (e.g., baselines) • It doesn’t directly account for variation in national abatement cost curves • It produces unbelievably large obligations for developed countries • The individual approach to “the right to development” is problematic • much of what is required for “development” are collective (public goods) • GDRs offers no guarantee that national policies will reflect underlying principles

  23. GDRs: political usefulness? • It could, in theory, form the basis of a global treaty • Hah! • In a “pledge and review” world, it can be used to measure national pledges against an equity benchmark • Requires some belief that its numbers are defensibly fair • It could provide the basis for domestic campaigns to increase national ambition

  24. GDRs: Questions • Does our overall method produce a result that is defensibly fair? • Is there a better way to define capacity? • Is there a better way to define responsibility? • Is there a better way to combine them? • Do our models of application (tons, dollars) make sense? • Does one make more sense than another? • How can our proposal be politically useful? • What problems are generic to any equity framework, and what are specific to GDRs?

More Related