kurt g del and the origins of computer science
Download
Skip this Video
Download Presentation
Kurt Gödel and the origins of computer science

Loading in 2 Seconds...

play fullscreen
1 / 47

Kurt G del and the origins of computer science - PowerPoint PPT Presentation


  • 131 Views
  • Uploaded on

Kurt Gödel and the origins of computer science. John W. Dawson, Jr. Pennsylvania State University York, PA U.S.A. Kurt Gödel (1906 –1978). Considered the greatest mathematical logician of the twentieth century, he was one of the founders of recursion theory.

loader
I am the owner, or an agent authorized to act on behalf of the owner, of the copyrighted work described.
capcha
Download Presentation

PowerPoint Slideshow about 'Kurt G del and the origins of computer science' - Gabriel


An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation

Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author.While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server.


- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - E N D - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -
Presentation Transcript
kurt g del and the origins of computer science

Kurt Gödel and the origins of computer science

John W. Dawson, Jr.

Pennsylvania State University

York, PA U.S.A.

kurt g del 1906 1978
Kurt Gödel (1906–1978)

Considered the greatest mathematical logician of the twentieth century, he was one of the founders of recursion theory.

A Princeton colleague of Alonzo Church and John von Neumann, his impact on computer science was seminal, but largely indirect.

works by g del of special relevance to computer science
Works by Gödel of special relevance to computer science
  • Completeness of first-order logic (1930)
  • Incompleteness of formal number theory (1931)
  • Papers on decision problems (1932–33)
  • Definition of the notion of general recur-sive function (IAS lectures, 1934; first published 1965)
slide4
“On the lengths of proofs” (1936)
  • “Some basic theorems on the founda-tions of mathematics, and their philo-sophical implications” (Gibbs Lecture, *1951)
  • Letter to von Neumann (*1956)
  • “A philosophical error in Turing’s work” (1972; first published 1974)

*First published posthumously in Gödel’s Collected Works

the 1930 completeness paper
The 1930 Completeness Paper
  • In his first published paper (a revision of his doctoral dissertation), Gödel stated the com-pleteness of first-order logic in the form: “Every valid formula of first-order logic [one true under every interpretation] is provable from the logical axioms.”
  • But as in the dissertation, he proved it in the form “Every formula is either refutable or satis-fiable.” He then extended the result to countable sets of formulas, to yield “A countable consistent set of formulas has a model”.
the strong completeness theorem
The Strong Completeness Theorem
  • The main focus of Gödel’s 1930 paper is that a formula of first-order logic is valid if and only if it is derivable using the rules of inference given earlier by Hilbert and Ackermann. But he actually proved more:
  • (Strong completeness) For any set Σ of first-order axioms, φ holds in every model of Σ if and only if φ is provable from Σ ( a result first stated explicitly by Abraham Robinson in 1951).
significance for computer science
Significance for computer science

The strong completeness theorem shows

that the rules of inference developed prior

to Gödel’s work are adequate for the pur-

pose of deriving all logical consequences of

a set of axioms. A computer incorporating

just those rules will thus be able to carry out

all such derivations.

completeness vs incompleteness
Completeness vs. incompleteness

The completeness theorem entails that the

statements provable in any first-order

axiomatization of number theory are those

that are true in all models of the axioms.

But for no recursive axiomatization will

those statements coincide with the state-

ments that are true of the natural numbers:

the g del rosser theorem
The Gödel-Rosser Theorem

Any recursive axiomatization A of arithmetic

must either be inconsistent (and so prove

every statement φ ) or else fail to prove both

some variable-free statement φand its

negation. Hence if A is consistent, it must

fail to prove some statement that is true of

the natural numbers.

slide11
The Gödel-Rosser Theorem is a limitative

result. In the context of computer science,

as is well known, Alan Turing used the

correspondence between computer pro-

grams and formal systems to recast it as

The Halting Problem: No recursive pro-cedure can correctly determine, for an arbitrarily given computer running any specified program, whether or not the computer will eventually come to a halt.

the larger significance of g del s incompleteness paper
The larger significance of Gödel’s incompleteness paper

For the development of computer science,

the proof Gödel gave of his incompleteness

results was more important than the

theorems themselves. Three aspects of

the proof were of particular significance:

slide13
His precise definition of the class of (what are now called) primitive recursive functions
  • His distinction between object language and metalanguage.
  • His idea of representing one data type (sequences of strings) by another type (numbers), thereby coding metatheo-retical notions as number-theoretic predicates.
slide14
In addition, as Martin Davis has remarked, the

overall structure of Gödel’s proof “looks very much

like a computer program” to anyone acquainted

with modern programming languages — unsur-

prisingly, since though “an actual … general-

purpose … programmable computer was still

decades in the future,” Gödel faced “many of the

same issues that those designing programming

languages and …writing programs in those

languages” face today.

the second incompleteness theorem
The second incompleteness theorem

As a further example of a numerical state-

ment that must be formally undecidable

within any consistent, recursive axioma-

tization of arithmetic, Gödel adduced a

numerical encoding of a statement asserting

the theory’s consistency.

philosophical significance of the incompleteness theorems
Philosophical significance of the incompleteness theorems

Much later, in his Gibbs Lecture to the American

Mathematical Society (1951),Gödel would suggest

that the incompleteness theorems are relevant to

the questions

  • whether the powers of the human mind exceed those of any machine, and
  • whether there are mathematical problems that are undecidable for the human mind.
special cases of the decision problem
Special cases of the decision problem

During the years 1932–33 Gödel turned his

attention to the decision problem — the

question whether there is an algorithm for

determining whether an arbitrary formula

of first-order logic is valid or not. He estab-

lished two results, concerning particular

prefixclasses of quantificational formulas:

slide19
He exhibited an algorithm for deciding the validity or invalidity of formulas in one quantifier-prefix class.
  • He showed that the (full) decision problem is reducible to that for formulas in another quantifier-prefix class.

Subsequently, on the basis of Church’s Thesis,

Church and Turing each demonstrated that the full

decision problem is algorithmically unsolvable.

extending the scope of the incompleteness theorems
Extending the scope of the incompleteness theorems

Gödel spent the academic year 1933–34 in

Princeton at the Institute for Advanced Study.

That spring, in a course of lectures on exten-

sions of his incompleteness results, he defined

the notion of general recursive function, based on

an idea suggested to him by Jacques Herbrand.

g del s definition and church s thesis
Gödel’s definition and Church’s Thesis

Gödel’s was one of several definitions later shown

to characterize the same class of functions.

On 19 April 1935, in a talk before a meeting of the

American Mathematical Society, Church pro-

pounded his Thesis:

The class so characterized consists of exactly

those functions informally thought of as being

effectively computable.

two points of note
Two points of note
  • In enunciating his Thesis, Church used the Gödel-Herbrand definition, rather than his own characterization of that class of functions (as those that are λ-definable).
  • Gödel himself was skeptical of Church’s Thesis, and only came to accept it in the wake of Turing’s analysis of the opera-tions performed by human computors.
g del s prescience i
Gödel’s prescience (I)

On 19 June 1935 Gödel made his last pre-

sentation to Karl Menger’s mathematical

colloquium. Titled “On the length of proofs”,

it appeared the following year as a two-page

article in the colloquium proceedings. It is

now regarded as the first announcement of

a “speed-up” theorem.

remarks
Remarks:
  • Gödel stated his result without proof. The first published proof was given by Sam Buss in 1994.
  • The measure of length Gödel used is the number of lines (inferences) in the proof, not the number of symbols.
  • It is unclear whether Gödel intended + and ∙ to be represented by function symbols or predicate symbols.
g del s prescience ii
Gödel’s Prescience (II)

Gödel did not pursue the ideas in his length-

of-proof paper, which seems to have been

an afterthought to his incompleteness

theorems.

Much later, in a letter to his terminally ill

friend von Neumann, Gödel made another

observation he did not follow up: The first

known formulation of the P = NP problem.

the gibbs lecture 1951
The Gibbs Lecture (1951)

In his Gibbs Lecture, Gödel attempted

to draw implications from the incom-

pleteness theorems concerning three

problems in the philosophy of mind:

slide31
Whether there are mathematical ques-tions that are “absolutely unsolvable” by any proof the human mind can conceive
  • Whether the powers of the human mind exceed those of any machine
  • Whether mathematics is our own creation or exists independently of the human mind
g del s conclusions
Gödel’s conclusions

With regard to the first two questions, Gödel

argued that “Either … the human mind (even

within the realm of pure mathematics)

infinitely surpasses the powers of any finite

machine, or else there exist absolutely

unsolvable diophantine problems”. He

believed the first alternative was more likely.

what g del didn t claim
What Gödel didn’t claim

Unlike commentators such as John Lucas

and Roger Penrose, Gödel did not assert

that the incompleteness theorems defini-

tively refute mechanism, nor (as Judson

Webb has asserted) that “the Church-Turing

thesis … is the principal bastion protecting

mechanism”.

slide34
As to the ontological status of mathematics,

Gödel claimed that the existence of abso-

lutely unsolvable problems would seem

“to disprove the view that mathematics is …

our own creation; for [a] creator necessarily

knows all properties of his creatures”. He

admitted that “we build machines and still

cannot predict their behavior in every detail”.

But that objection, he said, is “very poor”:

slide35
“For we don’t create … machines out of

nothing, but build them out of some

given material.”

It seems he recognized that hardware

may behave unpredictably, but not

software (!)

turing s contrary view 1948
Turing’s contrary view (1948)

“The view that intelligence in machinery is merely a reflection of that of its creator is … similar to the view that … credit for the discoveries of a pupil should be given to his teacher. In such a case the teacher [sh]ould be pleased with the success of his methods of education, but [sh]ould not claim the results themselves unless he ha[s] actually communicated them to his pupil” ---Alan Turing, “Intelligent machinery”

slide37
To put Gödel’s belief in perspective, note

that, unlike Turing or von Neumann, he was

never involved with the design or operation

of actual computers — even though it was at

the IAS that von Neumann built one of the

earliest computers.

Consider also the statement that computer

pioneer Howard Aiken made five years later:

slide38

“If it should turn out that the basic logics of a machine designed for the numerical solution of differential equations coincide with the logics of a machine intended to make bills for a department store, I would re-gard this as the most amazing coin-cidence I have ever encountered.”

g del s criticism of turing
Gödel’s criticism of Turing

Despite his high regard for Turing’s work,

late in his life Gödel claimed that Turing had

erred in arguing that mental procedures

cannot go beyond mechanical procedures.

Specifically, he charged that Turing had

completely disregarded “that mind, in its

use, is not static but constantly developing.”

in defense of turing
In defense of Turing

Contrary to Gödel’s charge, in his 1950

paper “Computing machinery and intelli-

gence”, Turing explicitly discussed learning

machines. There, too, he countered various

objections to the idea that machines could

simulate human thought, including the

“mathematical objection” based on the

incompleteness theorems.

some imponderables
Some imponderables

Gödel and Turing never met, nor did they

exchange any correspondence of sub-

stance. Gödel delivered his Gibbs Lecture

one year after the appearance of Turing’s

paper quoted above, and his criticism of

Turing came long after Turing’s death.

One must therefore wonder:

slide42
At the time of his Gibbs Lecture, was Gödel aware of Turing’s 1950 paper?
  • Gödel’s Gibbs Lecture was delivered less that three years before Turing’s death, just months before his prosecution for homosexuality, and it was not pub-lished until 1995. Did Turing ever become aware of its contents?
g del and emil post
Gödel and Emil Post

Emil Post was an important contributor to

recursion theory, and helped to initiate the

field of automata theory. Twenty years

before Gödel, he also conjectured (and

nearly proved) the incompleteness of formal

number theory. His outlook, however, was

very different from Gödel’s.

slide44
Post met Gödel in October of 1938.

Shortly afterward he wrote to Gödel to

expound further on his “near miss”. He

explained that he had set out to demonstrate

the existence of absolutely unsolvable prob-

lems, and thought he “saw a way of analyz-

ing ‘all finite processes of the human mind’ ”

that would establish incompleteness “in

general, … not just for Principia Mathema-

tica.”

slide45
Arguably, Post contributed more directly to

the development of computer science than

Gödel did. But as he himself conceded in

that same letter, “Nothing that I had done

could have replaced the splendid actuality of

your proof.” Sidetracked by his quest to

exhibit an absolutely unsolvable problem,

Post failed to give an example of one that

was undecidable in a particular formalism.

questions to ponder
Questions to ponder

If Gödel were alive today, what would he think of the role of computers in mathe-matics?

Would he approve of their use in providing numerical evidence for conjectures?

What would he think of computer-assisted proofs?

Would he maintain his belief in the mind’s superiority?

basic references
Basic References

Kurt Gödel, Collected Works (5 vols.), ed. Solomon Feferman et al. Oxford University Press, 1986–2003.

The Essential Turing, ed. B. Jack Copeland, Oxford University Press, 2004.

Solvability, Provability, Definability: The Collected Works of Emil L. Post, ed. Martin Davis. Birkhäuser, 1994.

ad