1 / 60

CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence

CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence. Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes Jan 26, 2012. Topics. More about assignment 3 Negation by failure and Horn Clause databases Closed world assumption First order logic continued Wumpus world model using FOL Jan 31 A few more details about hw3

vaughan
Download Presentation

CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CS 4100 Artificial Intelligence Prof. C. Hafner Class Notes Jan 26, 2012

  2. Topics • More about assignment 3 • Negation by failure and Horn Clause databases • Closed world assumption • First order logic continued • Wumpus world model using FOL Jan 31 • A few more details about hw3 • Test data available • loadInitialKB and processPercepts functions • Return an discuss assignments 1 and 2 • Converting FOL sentences to Normal Form • Unification • Automated reasoning in FOL: resolution, forward chaining, backward chaining

  3. Sketch of Forward Chaining Algorithm (version 1 assumes the initial KB is fully expanded) ALGORITHM (recursive): processPercepts(‘percepts file’) uses KBase -- a knowledge base of definite clauses for each new percept p PLForwardChain(p) #use a recursive "helper function" PLForwardChain(percept) if percept is already in KBase, return else add percept to KBase for r in rules where conclusion of r is not already in KBase if percept is a premise of r and all the other premises of r are known PLForwardChain(conclusion of r)

  4. Sketch of Forward Chaining Algorithm (version 2 drops this assumption) processPercepts(‘percepts file’) uses KBase -- a knowledge base of definite clauses for each new percept p PLForwardChain(p) #use a recursive "helper function" PLForwardChain(percept) if percept is already in KBase, return else add percept to KBase for r in rules where conclusion of r is not already in KBase if percept is a premise of r and allTrue(premises of r) #all premises are known or provable PLForwardChain(conclusion of r) allTrue(premises) for p in premises if p is already in Kbase continue if p is not provable return false return true

  5. Return to FOL: Meaning and truth (review) • Sentences of FOL are true with respect to a model and an interpretation • A model for a FOL language is a “world” of objects (domainelements) and relations among them (compare with propositional logic model) • InterpretationIspecifies referents for constantsymbols→objects predicatesymbols→relations functionsymbols→ functions • For an atomic sentence, the interpretation I(P(term1,...,termn) )= true iff the objects I(term1)..., I(termn) are in the relationI(P)

  6. Meaning and truth in first-order logic (cont.) • Complex sentences: truth is defined using the same truth tables: I(S1 S2) = true iff I (S1) = true and I (S2) = true. • I(x [S]) = true iff for every object o in the modelI (S[x/C]) = true whenI (C) = o • I( x [S]) = is true iff there is at least one object o in the model such that:I (S[x/C]) = true whenI (C) = o

  7. Models for FOL: Example symbols: constant relation function

  8. Quantification examples: • <variables> <sentence> Everyone at NU is smart: x [ At(x,NU)  Smart(x) ] • x P is true in a model m iff P is true with x being each possible object in the model • Roughly speaking, equivalent to the conjunction of all instantiations of P At(KingJohn,NU)  Smart(KingJohn)  At(Richard,NU)  Smart(Richard)  At(NUS,NU)  Smart(NUS)

  9. A common mistake to avoid • Typically,  is the main connective with  • Common mistake: using  as the main connective with : x At(x,NU)  Smart(x) means “Everyone is at NU and everyone is smart”

  10. Quantification examples (cont.) • <variables> <sentence> • Someone at NU is smart: • x [At(x,NU)  Smart(x)] • xP is true in a model m iff P is true with x being some possible object in the model • Roughly speaking, equivalent to the disjunction of all instantiations of P At(KingJohn,NU)  Smart(KingJohn)  At(Richard,NU)  Smart(Richard)  At(NU,NU)  Smart(NU)  ...

  11. Another common mistake to avoid • Typically,  is the main connective with  • Common mistake: using  as the main connective with : x At(x,NU)  Smart(x) is true if there is no one who at NU!

  12. Properties of quantifiers • x y is the same as yx • x y is the same as yx • x y is not the same as yx • x y Loves(y, x) • “There is a person who is loved by everyone in the world” • xy Loves(y, x) • “Everyone in the world is loved by at least one person” • Quantifier duality: each can be expressed using the other(cf DeMorgan laws) • x Likes(x,IceCream) == x Likes(x,IceCream) • x Likes(x,Broccoli) == xLikes(x,Broccoli)

  13. Equality • term1 = term2is true under a given interpretation if and only if term1and term2refer to the same object • E.g., definition of Sibling in terms of Parent: x,ySibling(x,y)  [(x = y)  m,f [  (m = f)  Parent(m,x)  Parent(f,x)  Parent(m,y)  Parent(f,y)]] • We will use a different notation for equality: =(x, y) • makes programming simpler

  14. A model M for the kinship domain • Individuals: J K L M N O P Q R • Functions: mom[1] : mom(N)  M • Relations[arity] • fem[1] = {M, Q} • par[2] = {[M, N], [N, R] . . } • sib[2] = {[M, O], [P, J], [J, P]} --------------------Interpretation I ----------------------- • Constants: John, Mary, Sue, Tom .. .. • I(Mary) = M, I(Sue) = Q, . . . • Function symbol: Mother, I(Mother) = mom • Relation symbols: Female, Parent, Sibling I(Female) = fem, I(Parent) = par, I(Sibling) = sib

  15. Using FOL The kinship domain: • Brothers are siblings x,y Brother(x,y)  Sibling(x,y) • “Sibling” is symmetric x,y Sibling(x,y) Sibling(y,x) • One's mother is one's female parent m,c =(Mother(c) , m) (Female(m) Parent(m,c)) • Some mothers are over 40 years old  m, x [=(Mother(x), m) ^ > (Age(m), 40) ]

  16. Knowledge Engineering: Choice of Representations • Human(Bob) vs. ISA(Bob, Human) • Green(B21) vs. Color(B21, Green) The choice affects the generality at which concepts can be expressed Inheritance rule: x,y,z ISA(x, y) ^ ISA(y, z)  ISA(x, z) Two blocks are the same color: x Color(B21, x) ^ Color(B22, x)

  17. Informal quiz on use of FOL to represent “common sense” knowledge • All apples are red • Some apples are red (“some” means at least one) • All apples contain (some) worms • Some apples contain (some) worms • Every person is mortal • Every person is male or female (but not both)

  18. Wumpus world in FOL • First step: define constants, function symbols, predicate symbols to express the facts • Percept(data, t) means: at step t, the agent perceived the data where data is a vector: • [Stench, Breeze, Glitter] • Ex: Percept([None, Breeze, None],2] • At(Agent, s, t) means: agent is at square s at step t • Ex: At(Agent, [2,1], 2]

  19. Some Wumpus axioms Axiom to interpreting perceptions in context x,t At(Agent, x, t) ^ Breeze(t)  Breezy(x) Definitional axiom: s,g,t Percept([s, Breeze, g], t)  Breeze(t) Diagnostic Axiom x Breezy(x)  z Adjacent(z, x) ^ Pit(z) Causal Axiom: z Pit(z)  (x Adjacent(z, x)  Breezy(x)) World model axioms: Adjacent([1,1],[2,1]) etc. x,y Adjacent(x, y)  Adjacent(y,x)

  20. Interacting with FOL KBs • Suppose a wumpus-world agent is using an FOL KB and perceives a smell and a breeze (but no glitter) at t=5: Tell(KB,Percept([Smell,Breeze,None],5)) – use forward chaining Ask(KB,a BestAction(a,5)) - use backward chaining BC Query: does the KB entail some best action at t=5? • Answer: {a/Shoot} ← substitution (binding list) • Given a sentence S and a substitution σ, • Sσ denotes the result of plugging σ into S; e.g., S = Smarter(x,y) σ = {x/Sue,y/Bill} Sσ = S {x/Sue,y/Bill} = Smarter(Sue,Bill) • Ask(KB,S) returns σ such that KB╞ Sσ

  21. Knowledge engineering in FOL • Identify the task Assemble the relevant knowledge • Decide on a vocabulary of predicates, functions, and constants (a logical language L) • Encode general knowledge about the domain • Encode a description of the specific problem instance • Pose queries to the inference procedure and get answers Debug the knowledge base

  22. Negation by failure and CWA A closed world is a world where every fact that is not known is false. Real-world examples: databases Query: Does American Airlines fly from Boston to Tampa? If no DB records of such flights answer NO (consider a Horn clause KB of food “likes”) Query: Does Sam like cheeseburgers? not a known “fact” not provable by “rules” no way to prove he does not, but we say “NO”

  23. Conversion to CNF • Everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone: x [ y [Animal(y) Loves(x,y)] y Loves(y,x) ] • 1. Eliminate biconditionals and implications x [ y [Animal(y) Loves(x,y) ] yLoves(y,x) ] • 2. Move  inwards: x p ≡x p,  x p ≡x p x [y [ (Animal(y) Loves(x,y))] y Loves(y,x) ] x [y [Animal(y) Loves(x,y) ]y Loves(y,x) ] No more negated quantifiers

  24. Conversion to CNF contd. • Rename variables: each quantifier should use a different one x [y [Animal(y) Loves(x,y) ]y Loves(y,x) ] x1 [ y1 [ Animal(y1) Loves(x1,y1) ] y2Loves(y2,x1) ] 4. Skolemize: Each existential variable is replaced by a Skolem function of the enclosing universally quantified variables: x1 [ (Animal(F1(x1)) Loves(x1,F1(x1))) Loves(F2(x1),x1) ] • Drop universal quantifiers: (Animal(F1(x)) Loves(x,F1(x))) Loves(F2(x),x) • Distribute  over  Animal(F1(x)) Loves(F2(x),x) Loves(x,F1(x) ) Loves(F2(x),x)

  25. Class exercise

  26. Inference in FOL – Chapter 9 • Theoretical foundations • Inference by universal and existential instantiation • Unification • Resolution viewed as Generalized Modus Ponens • Practical implementation (forward and backward chaining)

  27. Notation A substitution is a set of variable-term pairs: {x/term, y/term, . . . }, often referred to using the symbol θ [theta]. No variable can occur more than once. For any term or formula A: Subst(θ, A) also written Aθ == the result of replacing each variable in A with the corresponding term. A term is a constant symbol, a variable symbol, or a function symbol applied to 0 or more terms. Def: A ground term is a term with no variables Def: A ground sentence is a sentence with no free variables

  28. Inference by Universal instantiation (UI) • Every instantiation of a universally quantified sentence is entailed by it: vα Subst({v/g}, α) for any variable v and ground term g • E.g., x King(x) Greedy(x)  Evil(x) yields: King(John) Greedy(John) Evil(John) King(Richard) Greedy(Richard) Evil(Richard) King(Father(John)) Greedy(Father(John)) Evil(Father(John)) . . .

  29. Inference by Existential instantiation (EI) • For any sentence α, variable v, and constant symbol k that does not appear elsewhere in the knowledge base: vα Subst({v/k}, α) • E.g., xCrown(x) OnHead(x,John) yields: Crown(C1) OnHead(C1,John) provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem constant

  30. To implement universal instantiation • All humans are mortal • Jack is human ---------------------------- • Jack is mortal R1. x Human(x)  Mortal(x) F1. Mortal(Jack) Let R1 be p  q, Let F1 be be p’ Modus ponens for FOL: If p and p’ unify, conclude q’ Unify means we can match p and p’ by a substitution. We then apply the same substitution to q to get q’

  31. Unification • Def: Two formulas A and B unify if there is a substitution θ such that Aθ = Bθ. • Ex: To unify A = Knows(John, x) and B = Knows(y, Mary) θ = {y/John, x/Mary } • θ is not unique! • To unify A = Knows(John,x) and B = Knows(y,z), θ1 = {y/John, x/z } or θ2 = {y/John, x/Sue, z/Sue} • The first unifier is more general than the second. • There is a single most general unifier (MGU) that is unique up to renaming of variables. MGU = { y/John, x/z } or {y/John, z/x }

  32. Most general unifier • Def: If θ1 is a unifier for formulas A and B, it is a MOST GENERAL UNIFIER (MGU) iff: • There is no other unifier θ2 for A and B such that Aθ1 subsumes Aθ2 • A formula F subsumes a formula G if there is a non-trivial substitution  such that F = G • A θ1 = Knows(John, z) Aθ2 = Knows(John, Sue) Aθ1 subsumes Aθ2 therefore θ2 = {y/John, x/Sue, z/Sue} is not a MGU.Note: what is  ??

  33. Class Exercise: Unification Examples Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Barak) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Barak)

  34. Unification • Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Barak) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Barak)

  35. Unification • Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Barak) {x/Barak,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Barak)

  36. Unification • Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Barak) {x/Barak,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}} Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Barak)

  37. Unification • Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Barak) {x/Barak,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}} Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Barak) {fail}

  38. The unification algorithm (Fig. 9.1)

  39. The unification algorithm (cont.)

  40. Application to reasoning Modus ponens says: Given p q and p Conclude: q In FOL: Given p  q and p’ (where p and p’ unify by θ) Conclude: qθ Suppose KB includes: x King(x) Greedy(x)  Evil(x) King(John) This won’t quite work since we have p1 ^ p2  q

  41. Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP)(follows from the resolution rule for FOL) ( p1 p2 …  pnq), p1', p2', … , pn' qθ p1' is King(John) p1 is King(x) p2' is Greedy(y) p2 is Greedy(x) θ is {x/John,y/John} q is Evil(x) q θ is Evil(John) • GMP used with KB of definite clauses (exactly one positive literal) • All variables assumed universally quantified • How do we get Greedy(y) in our KB ? where pi'θ = piθ for all i

  42. Soundness of GMP • Need to show that p1', …, pn', (p1 …  pn q) ╞ qθ provided that pi'θ = piθ for all p • Lemma: For any sentence p, we have p╞ pθ by UI • (p1 …  pn q) ╞ (p1 …  pn q)θ = (p1θ …  pnθ qθ) • p1', …, pn' ╞ (p1'  …  pn‘ ) θ ╞ p1'θ …  pn'θ • From 1 and 2, qθ follows by ordinary Modus Ponens Note: you should know the definitions of a sound inference procedures and a complete inference procedure.

  43. Forward Chaining in FOL (with the “explicit knowledge” assumption) • Assume percepts do not contain variables (may contain “generated symbol” constants) • Example: you see an unfamiliar dog in the building: Percept: Isa(G33, Dog) Assume KB includes: Isa(x, Dog)  Isa(x, Animal) • Add new percept to KB if not already believed • If percept UNIFIES with a rule premise (by some θ) and if all the other premises pθ are believed, add qθ to KB. • θ is {x/G33) and qθ is isa(G33, Animal)

  44. Backward Chaining • Given a definite clause KB and a query q’: • For any fact q in KB that unifies with q’, return θ (or “YES” if θ = { } ) • For any rule in KB whose conclusion q unifies with q’: • If the rule’s premises p1 θ . . . pn θ can all be proved with a resulting substitution θ’, return COMPOSE(θ, θ’) • If no facts or rules result in a substitution, return “NO” • Note this can return multiple answers!

  45. Simple examples • KB: Likes(John, Pizza) Likes(Mary, Pizza) Likes(Sam, IceCream) • Query: Likes(John, Pizza) return YES • Query: Likes(Sam, Pizza) return NO (justified by CWA) • Query: Likes(x, Pizza) return a list of substitutions { {x/John} , {x/Mary} }

  46. More complex examples • Add to KB: Likes(y, Pizza)  Likes(y, Spaghetti) • Query: Likes(John, Spaghetti) • Query: Likes(Sam, Spaghetti) • Query: Likes(x, Spaghetti) • Query: Likes(x, y) Set of substitutions: { {x/John, y/Pizza}, {x/Mary, y/Pizza}, {x/Sam, y/IceCream}, {x/John, y/Spaghetti}, {x/Mary, y/Spaghetti} }

  47. Backward chaining algorithm SUBST(COMPOSE(θ1, θ2), p) = SUBST(θ2, SUBST(θ1, p))

  48. Backward Chaining: Example knowledge base • The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations. The country Nono, is an enemy of America, has some missiles, and all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American. • Prove that Col. West is a criminal

  49. Example knowledge base contd. ... it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations: American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Nono … has some missiles, i.e., x Owns(Nono,x)  Missile(x): Owns(Nono,M1) and Missile(M1) … all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missiles are weapons: Missile(x)  Weapon(x) An enemy of America counts as "hostile“: Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) West, who is American … American(West) The country Nono, an enemy of America … Enemy(Nono,America)

  50. Backward chaining example

More Related