1 / 27

Inference in first-order logic part 1

Inference in first-order logic part 1. Chapter 9 Modified by Vali Derhami. Outline. Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward chaining Backward chaining Resolution. Universal instantiation (UI).

Download Presentation

Inference in first-order logic part 1

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Inference in first-order logicpart 1 Chapter 9 Modified by Vali Derhami

  2. Outline • Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference • Unification • Generalized Modus Ponens • Forward chaining • Backward chaining • Resolution

  3. Universal instantiation (UI) • Subst(, a) denote the result of applying the substitution  to the sentence a. • Every instantiation of a universally quantified sentence is entailed by it: Here v is variable, and α is a sentence. vαSubst({v/g}, α) for any variable v and ground term (ترم بدون متغیر(g • E.g., x King(x) Greedy(x)  Evil(x) yields: {x/John}: King(John) Greedy(John) Evil(John) {x/Richard}: King(Richard) Greedy(Richard) Evil(Richard) {x/Father(John)}: King(Father(John)) Greedy(Father(John)) Evil(Father(John)). .

  4. Existential instantiation (EI) • For any sentence α, variable v, and constant symbol k that does not appear elsewhere in the knowledge base: vα Subst({v/k}, α) • E.g., xCrown(x) OnHead(x,John) yields: Crown(C1) OnHead(C1,John) provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem constant توجه شود C1 نباید در هیچ کجای دیگر از KB امده باشد. پایگاه دانش جدید با پایگاه دانش قدیمی هم ارز نیست، لیکن هم ارز استنباطی است. اگر پایگاه دانش اصلی ارضا پذیر باشد، پایگاه دانش جدید نیز ارضا پذیر است.

  5. Reduction to propositional inference Suppose the KB contains just the following: x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) King(John) Greedy(John) Brother(Richard,John) • Instantiating the universal sentence in all possible ways, we have: King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) King(Richard)  Greedy(Richard)  Evil(Richard) King(John) Greedy(John) Brother(Richard,John) • The new KB is propositionalized: • proposition symbols are King(John), Greedy(John), Evil(John), King(Richard), etc.

  6. Reduction contd. • Every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to preserve entailment (هر پایگاه دانش مرتبه اول می تواند گزاره ای شود به نحوی که ایجاب حفظ شود.) • (A ground sentence is entailed by new KB iff entailed by original KB) • Idea: Propositionalize KB and query, apply resolution, return result • Problem: with function symbols, there are infinitely many ground terms, • e.g., Father(Father(Father(John)))

  7. Reduction contd. Theorem: Herbrand (1930). If a sentence αis entailed by an FOL KB, it can be entailed by a finite subset of the propositionalized KB Idea: For n = 0 to ∞ do create a propositional KB by instantiating with depth 1-n terms see if α is entailed by this KB بدین معنی که ابتدا زیر مجموعه گزاره ای از پایگاه دانش با عمق یک (ثوابت جا گذاری شده و برای توابع تنها عمق اول لحاظ شود) ایجاد و استنتاج انجام اگر نتیجه ایجاب شد که تمام است وگرنه برای عمق دوم و .... Problem: works if α is entailed, loops if α is not entailed • Theorem: Turing (1936), Church (1936):The question of entailment for first-order logic is semidecidable(نیمه تصمیم پذیر)—that is, algorithms exist that say yes to every entailed sentence, but no algorithm exists that also says no to every nonentailed sentence.

  8. Problems withpropositionalization • Propositionalization seems to generate lots of irrelevant sentences. • E.g., from: x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) King(John) y Greedy(y) Brother(Richard,John) • it seems obvious that Evil(John), but propositionalization produces lots of facts such as Greedy(Richard) that are irrelevant

  9. Unificationیکسان سازی • We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ such that King(x) and Greedy(y) match King(John) and Greedy(John) θ = {x/John,y/John} works Unify(p,q) = θ if Subst(θ,p) = Subst(θ,q) p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)

  10. Unification • We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) θ = {x/John,y/John} works • Unify(p,q) = θ if Subst(θ,p) = Subst(θ,q) p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)

  11. Unification • We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) θ = {x/John,y/John} work • Unify(α,β) = θ if Subst(θ,α) = Subst(θ,β) p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)

  12. Unification • We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) θ = {x/John,y/John} works • Unify(α,β) = θ if Subst(θ,α) = Subst(θ,β) p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}} Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)

  13. Unification • We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y) θ = {x/John,y/John} works • Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ p q θ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}} Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ) {fail} • Standardizing apart (جداسازی استاندارد) eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ) • {x/Oj, z17/John}

  14. Unification • To unify Knows(John,x) and Knows(y,z), θ = {y/John, x/z } or θ= {y/John, x/John, z/John} • The first unifier is more general than the second. • There is a single most general unifier (MGU) (عمومی ترین یکسان ساز)that is unique up to renaming of variables. MGU = { y/John, x/z }

  15. The unification algorithm

  16. The unification algorithm

  17. Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP) p1', p2', … , pn', ( p1 p2 …  pnq) qθ Example: p1' is King(John) p1 is King(x) p2' is Greedy(y) p2 is Greedy(x) θ is {x/John,y/John} q is Evil(x) q θ is Evil(John) • GMP used with KB of definite clauses (exactly one positive literal) (Clause: ترکیب OR از لیترالها) definite clauses:Horn clauses with exactly one positive literal • All variables assumed universally quantified (فرض میشود همه متغیرها سور عمومی دارند) where pi'θ = piθ for all i , pi,p’I , q and atomic sentence

  18. Soundness of GMP • Need to show that p1', …, pn', (p1 …  pn q) ╞ qθ provided that pi'θ = piθ for all i • Lemma: For any sentence p, we have p╞ pθ by UI • (p1 …  pn q) ╞ (p1 …  pn q)θ = (p1θ …  pnθ qθ) • p1', \; …, \;pn' ╞ p1'  …  pn' ╞ p1'θ …  pn'θ • pi'θ= piθ • From 1 and 2 and 3 , qθ follows by ordinary Modus Ponens

  19. Example knowledge base • The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile (متخاصم)nations. The country Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles (موشک), and all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American. • قانون می گوید که برای یک آمریکایی فروش اسلحه به کشورهای متخاصم جرم می باشد. کشور نونو که یکی از دشمنهای امریکا هستتعدادی موشک دارد و همه این موشکلها توسط کلنل وست که امریکایی هست به آنها فروخته شده است. • Prove that Colonel West is a criminal(مجرم)

  20. Example knowledge base contd. ... it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations: R1: American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Nono … has some missiles, i.e., x Owns(Nono,x)  Missile(x): Owns(Nono,M1) and Missile(M1) … all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West R2: Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missiles are weapons: R3: Missile(x)  Weapon(x) An enemy of America counts as "hostile“: R4: Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) West, who is American … American(West) The country Nono, an enemy of America … Enemy(Nono,America)

  21. Example knowledge base contd. R1: American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) R2: Missile(x1)  Owns(Nono,x1)  Sells(West,x1,Nono) R3: Missile(x2)  Weapon(x2) R4: Enemy(x3,America)  Hostile(x3) Owns(Nono,M1) Missile(M1) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  22. Forward chaining proof

  23. Forward chaining proof • R2: Missile(x1)  Owns(Nono,x1)  Sells(West,x1,Nono) • R3: Missile(x2)  Weapon(x2) • R4: Enemy(x3,America)  Hostile(x3) • Owns(Nono,M1) • Missile(M1) • American(West) • Enemy(Nono,America) {x3/Nono}, {x2/M1}, {x1/M1}

  24. Forward chaining proof • R1: American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) • {x/west, y/M1, z/Nono}

  25. Forward chaining algorithm

  26. Properties of forward chaining • Sound and complete for first-order definite clauses • Datalog clauses= first-order definite clauses + no functions • FC terminates for Datalog in finite number of iterations • May not terminate in general if α is not entailed • This is unavoidable: entailment with definite clauses is semidecidable (نیمه تصمیم پذیر)

  27. Efficiency of forward chaining Incremental forward chaining: no need to match a rule on iteration k if a premise wasn't added on iteration k-1  match each rule whose premise contains a newly added positive literal Matching itself can be expensive: Database indexing allows O(1) retrieval of known facts • e.g., query Missile(x) retrieves Missile(M1) Forward chaining is widely used in deductive (استقرایی) databases

More Related