1 / 31

Vagueness and Indiscriminability by Failure

Vagueness and Indiscriminability by Failure. Ariel Cohen Ben-Gurion University Israel . The Sorites. A sequence of elements: a 1 …a n For all 0<i<n , a i is indiscriminable from a i+1 . For some (vague) property P : P(a 1 ) and  P(a n ) .

nan
Download Presentation

Vagueness and Indiscriminability by Failure

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Vagueness and Indiscriminability by Failure Ariel Cohen Ben-Gurion University Israel

  2. The Sorites • A sequence of elements: a1…an • For all 0<i<n, ai is indiscriminable from ai+1. • For some (vague) property P: P(a1) and P(an). • Intuitively: a1 is discriminable from an. • Intuitively: there is some cut-off point i dividing Ps from Ps. • Hence: ai is discriminable from ai+1. Contradiction!

  3. Epistemic Solution • There is a cut-off point i. • But i is unknown/unknowable. • Hence, for all 0<i<n, ai is indiscriminable from ai+1.

  4. Supervaluation Solution • There is a cut-off point i. • But for no i does it follow that i is the cut-off point. • Hence, for all 0<i<n, ai is indiscriminable from ai+1.

  5. What is Indiscriminability? • The paradox, then, hinges on what we take indiscriminability to mean. • A definition is required which is compatible with: • the solutions to the sorites; • our intuitions. • Specifically: There is a cut-off point, but this does not lead to contradiction.

  6. 1. Reflexivity Every individual is indiscriminable from itself.

  7. 2. Symmetry If ais indiscriminable from b , then b is indiscriminable from a.

  8. 3. Weak Transitivity • Indisc. is not transitive: otherwise, a1would be indisc. from an • Instead—“weak” transitivity: If a is discriminable from b, then for all c, c is discriminable from a or from b . • Weak transitivity is entailed by transitivity • Weak transitivity can be shown to entail the existence of the cut-off point: If a1 and an are discriminable, there is a cut-off point i where ai is discriminable from ai+1.

  9. 4. Weak Substitutivity • Indisc. is not substitutive: otherwise, if P(a1), it would follow that P(an). • Instead—“weak” substitutivity: If P(a) but P(b), then ais discriminable from b. • Weak substitutivity is entailed by substitutivity.

  10. 5. Contextual Restriction • Weak substitutivity only applies to a “relevant” set of discriminating properties. • For example, P cannot be the indiscriminability relation itself, or indisc. would become transitive. • In the sorites: only the vague predicate in question is relevant for discrimination.

  11. Red • Every two consecutive tiles are indiscriminable with respect to their redness. • They are discriminable with respect to other properties, e.g. their size or location. • But these properties are not contextually relevant, hence do not make the tiles discriminable with respect to their redness.

  12. Rich • If a has one cent more than b, they are indiscriminable with respect to richness. • Although they are not indiscriminable in an absolute sense: they have different sums of money (and different names, hair colors, etc.)

  13. Direct, Pairwise Indiscriminability • Reflexive • Symmetric But: • Not weakly transitive • Not weakly substitutive Hence, not a good definition

  14. Indiscriminability by Failure • Based on Cohen and Makowsky's (1993) Equality by Failure. • Two elements are equal by failure iff they cannot be proved to be different. • Similar to Negation by Failure: if we cannot prove that something is true, we conclude that it is false.

  15. Equality Axioms 1. Reflexivity: x x=x 2. Symmetry: x y( x=yy=x) 3. Transitivity: x y z(( x=yy=z)x=z) 4. (functional substitutivity) 5. Predicate substitutivity: For every k-ary predicate symbol P (apart from ‘=‘) and every 1ik: x y z1...zi-1 zi+1...zk (x=y  (P(z1...zi-1,x,zi+1...zk) P(z1...zi-1,y,zi+1...zk)))

  16. Indiscriminability Axioms Change every = to DISC(,), and apply contraposition to simplify:

  17. DS 1. AX1: x DISC(x,x) 2. AX2: x y( DISC(y,x)DISC(x,y)) 3. AX3: x yz (DISC(x,z)(DISC(x,y)DISC(y,z))) 4. (AX4) 5. AX5: For every k-ary predicate symbol P (apart from DISC) and every 1ik: x y z1...zi-1 zi+1...zk ( (P(z1...zi-1,x,zi+1...zk) P(z1...zi-1,y,zi+1...zk)) DISC(x,y))

  18. • A consistent set of propositions (that do not contain DISC), representing what is known (epistemic theories) or definite (supervaluation theories). • In a “bare bones” sorites: ={P(a1),P(an)}

  19. Indiscriminability by Failure Defined • Let  be a consistent set of propositions. • Then ais indiscriminable by failure from b with respect to  iff DS| DISC(a,b)

  20. Indiscriminability of Indiscernibles DS|= DISC(a,b) iff there is some property  s.t DS|= (a) and DS|= (b)

  21. 1. Reflexivity • By AX1, for every a, DS|=DISC(a,a) • By the consistency of : DS|DISC(a,a)

  22. 2. Symmetry • Suppose indisc. by failure were not symmetric. Then, for some a, b: DS|DISC(a,b) yet DS|=DISC(b,a) • But, by AX2: DS|=DISC(a,b) • A contradiction • Hence, indisc. by failure is symmetric

  23. 3. Weak Transitivity • Indisc. by failure is not transitive • For example: • ={P(a),P(c)} • DS|DISC(a,b) andDS|DISC(b,c) • yet DS|=DISC(a,c) • But weak transitivity follows directly from AX3

  24. 4. Weak Substitutivity • Indisc. by failure is not substitutive • For example: • ={P(a)} • DS|DISC(a,b) • yet DS|P(b) • But weak substitutivity follows directly from AX5.

  25. 5. Contextual Restriction Follows from the definition: indisc. by failure is defined relative to 

  26. Helping to Solve the Sorites • Indisc. by failure can be superimposed on an epistemic or supervaluation theory to solve the sorites. • As desired, the existence of a cut-off point is entailed, yet no contradiction follows.

  27. Two Consecutive Elements are Indiscriminable • “Bare bones” sorites: ={P(a1),P(an)} • Hence, for all 1<i<n: DS|P(ai) DS|P(ai) • Therefore, for all 0<i<n: DS|DISC(ai,ai+1)

  28. a1 is Discriminable from an • DS|= P(a1) • DS|= P(an) • By weak substitutivity: • DS|= DISC(a1,an)

  29. A Cut-off Point Exists • By repeated applications of weak transitivity: • DS|= DISC(a1,a2)  DISC(a2,a3)...DISC(an-1,an)

  30. No Contradiction • All consecutive pairs of elements are indiscriminable • There is a cut-off point i where ai is discriminable from ai+1 • Is this a contradiction? • No: The existence of a cut-of point follows from , but it does not follow for any i that ai is discriminable from ai+1

  31. Conclusion • Indisc. by failure is an intuitively plausible definition of indiscriminability: reflexive, symmetric, weakly transitive, weakly substitutive, and contextually restricted. • In the sorites, it entails the existence of a cut-off point, yet does not lead to contradiction. • Hence, it is the right sort of indisc. to be incorporated into a solution to the sorites.

More Related