1 / 47

Rick Chappell, Ph.D. Professor Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics

University of Wisconsin – Madison. Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics. Equivalence Trials: a Horse of a Different Color. Rick Chappell, Ph.D. Professor Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics University of Wisconsin Medical School chappell@stat.wisc.edu.

jewell
Download Presentation

Rick Chappell, Ph.D. Professor Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. University of Wisconsin – Madison Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics Equivalence Trials: a Horse of a Different Color Rick Chappell, Ph.D. Professor Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics University of Wisconsin Medical School chappell@stat.wisc.edu

  2. University of Wisconsin – Madison Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics D what? Choice of outcome scale in non-inferiority trials Rick Chappell Professor Department of Statistics and Department of Biostatistics and Medical Informatics University of Wisconsin chappell@stat.wisc.edu

  3. Outline I. Definition of Equivalence Trials with a Motivating Example II. Choosing the Null Hypothesis III. Consequences of the Choice IV. One way to avoid the Choice - “Mixed Hypotheses” (with Xiaodan Wei) V. Consequences of Not Trying to Find an Effect

  4. I. A Motivating Example - SPORTIF III (Darius, 2002) Company: AstraZeneca Comparison: H 376/95 (Ximelagatran) vs. Warfarin Treatment and Followup: Up to twenty-six months Outcome: Stroke and other Events Measured by annual incidence rate Type:Equivalency, margin 2% per year (6% vs. 4%) Sample size:3000 patients

  5. Definition of Equivalence Trial • Consider treatment rate T and control rate C: • A Superiority Trial examines the treatment effect • C - T attempts to show it to be positive (when small values • are good). • A higher sample size n yields more power to precisely • estimate C – T and detect a difference in effects.

  6. An Equivalence (non-inferiority, active control) Trial examines C – T and attempts to show it to be not too small. • Naively, one can put a confidence interval on C - T and claim success if it does contain 0. The chance of this is maximized with lower n.

  7. Solution Require that trial limits margin to be not less than a "prespecified [negative] degree of inferiority" D [ICH E-3], C - T D . Temple and Ellenberg (2002) point out that this is a "not-too-much-inferiority trial". Here also a higher n, by giving more precision to estimate C - T, raises the chance of success.

  8. II. Specifying the Null Hypothesis Hypotheses in Superiority Trials H0: C - T = 0 (Treatment may have no effect) vs. HA: C - T > 0 (Treatment has Good Effect) Hypotheses in Equivalence Trials H0 : C - T < D (Treatment might be much worse) vs. HA : C - T D (Treatment isn’t much worse)

  9. Ways Effects can be Defined for a Time-to-Event Trial 1. Survival function S(t) at all followup times 2. Hazard function λ(t) at all followup times 3. Event rate by a given time 4. Median time to event H0 in a superiority trial is the same for definitions 1. and 2. Definitions 3. and 4. are weaker, but are implied by 1. and 2.

  10. "In Superiority Trials, all Null Hypotheses are the Same but all Alternatives are Different." - Tolstoy?

  11. For example, SC (t) – ST (t) = D lC (t) – lT (t) = D' medianC – medianT = D'' are in general all incompatible unless D = D' = D'' = 0. And Chen (2000) gives methods for testing equivalence of differences of proportions, products of productions, and odds ratios. 18

  12. These hypotheses also are incompatible unless margins are zero. This is not the case in equivalence studies, so we must pick the scale carefully. This ought to be the scale on which the specified margin is relevant. It may not result in the most convenient statistical analysis.

  13. A Motivating Example - SPORTIF III (Darius, 2002) Company: AstraZeneca Comparison: H 376/95 vs. Warfarin Treatment and Followup: Up to twenty-six months Outcome: Stroke and other Events Measured by annual incidence rate Type:Equivalency, margin 2% per year (6% vs. 4%) Sample size:3000 patients

  14. In the SPORTIF example, outcome is annual incidence rate, approximately the yearly hazard λ, so that the hypotheses are H0: lC - lT < -2% per year vs. HA: lC - lT -2% per year

  15. If event rates are constant then λis just the exponential • rate parameter, estimated by • h = Σδi / Σ fi , • where δi is an event indicator, fiis the followup time, and summation is over all subjects. • But typically the event rate will change with followup. • Then λ becomes an average annual rate over two years. • How to estimate it efficiently - using full two years of data? • What if followup varies? • How to estimate it robustly - not assuming any parametric • distribution?

  16. III. Consequences of the Choice(s) Here, we chose • The noninferiority margin, D = -2%/year; and • The scale of comparison in H0, the annual incidence rate (approximately, the hazard). There is much literature on choice #1 but almost none on #2.

  17. Choosing D = -2%/year: D should be smaller than the original estimated effect of Warfarin, so that if the event rate with Warfarin is 4% reduced from say 7% it would be nonsensical to consider Δ ≤ -3%. That would imply that therapeutic equivalence could be as bad as no treatment. But how do we choose Scale of comparison?

  18. Scale choice and balanced randomization Consider the simple normal two-sample constant variance case:XiT ~ iidN(T, 2) XiC ~ iidN(C, 2)Then the usual (unstandardized) test statistic for superiority is the difference in sample means. Obviously, the allocation which minimizes its variance is 1:1.

  19. Suppose we are designing an equivalence trial to test the hypothesisH0 : C - T <  .Then the optimal allocation is still 1:1.  However, if we want to testH0 : C / T < * ,which is equivalent to H0 : C - * ×T <0instead, then the optimal allocation is *: 1 in favor of the control group - a big difference.

  20. Scale choice and power Suppose, in a trial with binary “failure” outcome, we are deciding between the null hypothesis of additive noninferiority H0: pT - pC < .004 and that of multiplicative noninferiority H0: pT / pC < 1.5. These are equal at pC = .008. Should power be the same for HA: pT = pC = .008?

  21. Answer: no (surprisingly, to me and the trial’s principal investigator). For proportions less than .01, the range in which we are interested, the hypothesis of multiplicative noninferiority is much more demanding and requires a larger sample size: About 21,000 instead of 14,000!

  22. IV. An Unusual Choice of Scale for the Sake of Clinical Relevance We may be interested in equivalence on different scales depending on the parameter’s size. For example, consider a trial with a binary outcome whose rates in two groups are p1 and p2 . We might be interested in their difference for small p1 or their ratio for large p1. If so, we could have a pair of mixed hypotheses:

  23. where Δ1 and Δ2 are the equivalence limits for the difference and ratio. π* is the point at which the null hypothesis changes from the difference to the ratio test. We set π* = Δ1 / (Δ2 – 1) for continuity. The treatments are equivalent if equivalence holds on either the additive or multiplicative scale. Alternatively, we could require both to hold.

  24. To derive the test statistic, first rotate and center H0 to make it symmetric about the vertical axis: where B is the rotation matrix and (x , y ) are the new parameters translated from (p1 , p2).Now the null hypothesis is H0 : y = tan( )|x| .

  25. Let X1 and X2be independent variables come from Bin(n, p1) and Bin(n, p2) distribution. Let Estimate the rotated parameter (x, y) and the covariance matrix as: Consider the test statistic

  26. M converges to the standard normal distribution at all differentiable points of H0. • At points far from π* , M is equivalent to statistics from the relevant difference or normal test. • But at π* , M is converges to a mixture of normal and half-normal distributions. This can be shown by deriving results for a hyperbolic H0 and letting the hyperbola converge to a bent line.

  27. V. Consequences of “Not Trying to Find an Effect” Leads to questions about other notions of quality in clinical trials besides sample size: - noncompliance - drug impurity - loss to follow-up - enrollment of ineligibles - other protocol violations

  28. Obviously we want to minimize protocol violations in all trials. However, they have fundamentally different effects depending on the type of study they afflict. • In Superiority Trials conducted with proper randomization and blinding, these violations degrade the treatment effect • C - T and are thus conservative: they bias results towards a conclusion of no effect. • In Equivalence Trials, even with proper randomization and • blinding, these violations can degrade the treatment effect and are thus anti-conservative: they can bias results towards a conclusion of equivalence. 8

  29. Intent to Treat RevisitedIs it still the ironclad standard for primary analysis? "No participants should be withdrawn from the analysis due to lack of adherence. The price to be paid is a possible decrease in power." - Friedman, Furberg and DeMets, referring to superiority trials. General agreement, including in ICH guidelines: "An analysis using all available data should be carried out for all studies intended to establish efficacy" [ICH E-3].

  30. “”Intent to Treat” Analysis in the presence of noncompliance • Has decreased power compared to situation with full compliance • and • Results in estimate of C - T biased towards 0 • - conservative in superiority trials • - anticonservative in equivalence trials

  31. "As Treated" Analysis in the presence of noncompliance • Also has decreased power compared to situation with full • compliance: • and • Biases the estimate of C - T in an unknown fashion • - ? in superiority trials • - ? in equivalence trials

  32. Recommendation: •  Stick to Intent to Treat in equivalence trials but • Take Care to maximize quality of the data • Pay Attention to patterns of quality during the trial • Summarize aspects of quality in the report • Quality "Before, During and After”.

  33. ICH E-9 says that in an equivalence trial, the role of the full analysis (intent-to-treat) data set "should be considered very carefully." What percent of noncompliance is unacceptable?

  34. ICH E-10 states: • "The trial should also be conducted with high quality • (e.g., good compliance, few losses to follow-up)." • It also has useful advice: • "The trial conduct should also adhere closely to • that of the historical trials." • That is, the design and patient population should be similar • to previous trials used to determine evidence of sensitivity • to drug effects. • My conclusion: • If noncompliance is less than that achieved in prior trials which showed efficacy, good. • But if not, beware (same logic as in choice of Δ).

  35. Other interesting problems: We don’t just want to know if Ximelagatran is noninferior to Warfarin, we want to know if it “works” - if it is better than Placebo. We infer about: Effect of Xi. vs. Pl. = Effect of Xi. Vs. Wa. + Effect of Wa. Vs. Pl.

  36. HISTORICAL TRIAL EQUIVALENCE TRIAL nH PATIENTS nE PATIENTS RANDOMIZATION RANDOMIZATION PLACEBO, nH /2 OLD DRUG, nH /2 OLD DRUG, nE /2 NEW DRUG, nE /2 ? COMPARE COMPARE 24

  37. Inference’s validity depends on randomization and comparison with past trial in order to estimate treatment effect without direct comparison with placebo • Past trials give Historical Evidence of Sensitivity to • Drug Effects (HESDE) • HESDE is relevant only if populations in two trials are • similar 23

  38. This contrasts with a superiority trial's validity, which depends upon randomization: arms are drawn from same population (Lachin, 1988). n Patients RANDOMIZATION Old Drug, n/2 New Drug, n/2 COMPARE

  39. But populations change: • Age distribution change • Other characteristics change • Adjuvant therapies arise • Earlier diagnosis is possible • The disease itself may change • These imply that we should use a recent trial for comparison.

  40. There is a problem with continuously comparing to the most recent trials: ”Equivalency Drift“ (referred to as “Bio-creep” in one FDA guidance).

  41. The Problem of Equivalency Drift +4% +4% Margin of Equivalency = 2% BENEFIT BENEFIT 0 0 DRUG 1 DRUG 2 DRUG 3 DRUG 4 DRUG 1 DRUG 3 DRUG 4 DRUG 2 EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT

  42. Another Thorny Consideration +4% Suppose you represent a drug manufacturer conducting a clinical trial and you know that the trial’s results would be used to help a future competitor show its drug to be effective. Then the narrower your confidence intervals, the easier you make it for your competitor! You are motivated to make your results as imprecise as possible, while still permitting FDA approval. BENEFIT 0 DRUG 1 DRUG 2 EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT

  43. One last (favorable!) consequence +4% Suppose have multiple alternative hypotheses of equivalence and require them all to hold. Then the naïve individual testing approach is conservative. BENEFIT 0 DRUG 1 DRUG 2 EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT EQUIVALENT

  44. References Chen, J.J., Tsong, Y., and Kang, S. “Tests for equivalence or non-inferiority between two proportions. Drug Information Journal. 34, pp. 569-578 (2000). Friedman, L.M., Furberg, C., and DeMets, D.L. Fundamentals of Clinical Trials, Springer-Verlag, New York (1998). Halperin, J.L. “Ximelagatran compared with warfarin for prevention of thromboembolism in patients with nonvalvular atrial fibrillation: Rationale, objectives, and design of a pair of clinical studies and baseline patient characteristics (SPORTIF III and V).” Am. Heart J. 146, pp. 431-8 (2003). International Conference on Harmonisation of Technical Requirements for Registration of Pharmaceuticals for Human Use. Guidances E3: Structure and Content of Clinical Study Reports (1995); E9: Statistical Principles for Clinical Trials (1998); and E10: Choice of Control Group in Clinical Trials (2000). http://www.ich.org/ich5e.html#Reports Lachin, J.M. "Statistical properties of randomization in clinical trials.“ Controlled Clinical Trials9, pp. 289-311 (1988). Temple, R. and Ellenberg, SS. “Placebo-controlled trials and active-control trials in the evaluation of new treatments. Part 1: ethical and scientific issues.” Annals of Internal Medicine133, pp.455-63 (2000).

More Related