1 / 54

Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduction to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2016

Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduction to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2016. Dr Ron Gallagher ron.gallagher@monash.edu Week 10: Knowledge 2 (1 tutorial left) AT2: Essay Assignment ( Due: October 10, 10am) General Instructions Word Limit: 1250 words Value: 30%.

ffrye
Download Presentation

Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduction to Philosophy B Semester 2, 2016

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835)Introduction to Philosophy BSemester 2, 2016 Dr Ron Gallagher ron.gallagher@monash.edu Week 10: Knowledge 2 (1 tutorial left) AT2: Essay Assignment (Due: October 10, 10am) General Instructions Word Limit:1250 wordsValue:30%

  2. AT2: Essay Assignment (Due: October 10, 10am) General Instructions Word Limit:1250 words Value:30% Presentation Requirements:Your assignment should be presented in 12-point font and 1.5 or double-spaced. It will require references and a bibliography. Acceptable Formats: .doc or .rtf. (If you want to use some other format, clear it with your tutor beforehand.) Only submit an electronic copy; no hard copy submission required. File Name: Name your file using the following convention: [Question Number] [Surname] Example: "3Silva.doc," "5Smith.rtf", "1Jones.docx" Referencing and Citation: http://artsonline.monash.edu.au/philosophy/resources-for-undergraduate-students/ In your essay, you should try to fulfill the following requirements, especially the first: The essay must address the question asked. It should have a structure that is clear and organised to form a coherent argument. You should explain, in your own words, views and arguments in the prescribed readings that are relevant to the topic. Be careful to present these views fairly and accurately, with adequate citation detail. You should try to evaluate the arguments you have discussed, and in the process work out your own position. When you criticise a philosopher, try to think how she might reply to your objections. You must carefully identify all connections between your essay and the writings of others.

  3. Chicago style (numerical citation, footnotes) with bibliography at the end.

  4. Harvard style (in-text citation) with bibliography at the end.

  5. ESSAY MARKING CRITERIA - from ATS1835 Unit Guide

  6. ESSAY FAQs • The word limit is +/- 10% of 1250 words. • You are required to use at least one of the readings (not just the commentary or lecture slides) from the TSM Reader as your primary text. • You can reference the TSM Reader by page number, eg (Kane, 2007,TSM Reader p.56), you do not need to use the original page numbers of the individual papers in the Reader. • Begin the essay with a statement of YOUR thesis (eg You believe that machines do not think, and that Turing is wrong for such and such a reason and that Searle makes some good points) and how you are going to support it with arguments from the TSM Reader

  7. Essay Topics Due Monday 10th October 10am @1250 words 30% Write on one of the following topics. 1. Time Travel How can David Lewis's solution to the Grandfather paradox be used to solve the problem of the logically pernicious self-inhibitor discussed in your Unit Reader? Be sure to clearly lay out the problem and the solution to the grandfather paradox, and to draw the parallels between that paradox and the logically pernicious self-inhibitor problem. Discuss whether the solution to this problem seems as plausible as the solution to the Grandfather paradox. Required reading: David Lewis, 'The Paradoxes of Time Travel’ The Logically Pernicious Self‐inhibiter If time travel is possible, it must be possible to build ‘a logically pernicious self inhibiter’. Here is an example devised by John Earman: Imagine a rocket ship that can fire a probe into its own recent past. Suppose the rocket is programmed to fire the probe unless a safety switch is set to on, and that the safety switch is turned on if and only if the rocket detects the return of the probe. The rocket will fire the probe if and only if it does not fire the probe. That is impossible. (TSM Reader Page 10) That is: it can fire the probe and it can’t fire the probe.

  8. Earman asks us to consider a rocket ship that at some space-time point x can fire a probe that will travel along a timelike loop into the past lobe of x's light cone. Suppose the rocket is programmed to fire the probe unless a safety switch is on and the safety switch is turned on if and only if the "return" of the probe is detected by a sensing device with which the rocket is equipped (230-232). Is the probe fired or not? The answer is that it is fired if and only if it is not fired, which is logically absurd.This contradiction does not suffice to show that time travel per se is impossible. Rather the whole situation is impossible, and this includes assumptions about the programming of the rocket, the safety switch, the sensing device, and so forth. But, although the contradiction could be avoided by giving up some of these assumptions, Earman suggests that we have good evidence that rockets can be so programmed. Earman concludes, "Thus, although we cannot exclude closed timelike lines on logical grounds, we do have empirical reasons for believing that they do not exist in our world" (232). http://www.reasonablefaith.org/tachyons-time-travel-and-divine-omniscience#ixzz3E7PIvINl Earman, John (1972) Implications of causal propagation outside the null cone. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50 (3). pp. 222-237. ISSN 0004-8402 http://www.reasonablefaith.org/tachyons-time-travel-and-divine-omniscience

  9. Logical Paradoxes This sentence is false. Everything I say is always a lie. The Barber Paradox and the Set of All Sets. “The male barber shaves every man in town who does not shave himself. Who shaves the barber?” Assuming that every man in town has to get shaven, there is no escape from this dilemma. Bertrand Russell used this exercise to show that certain kinds of classification were impossible.

  10. Essay Topics..continued 2. Free Will Option 2 a): Soft determinists say free will is compatible with determinism, hard determinists deny this. Explain why soft determinists think free will is compatible with determinism and why hard determinists object to this. Which view do think is most plausible? Give your own examples that help illustrate/justify your points. Explain your reasons. Required reading David Lewis, 'The Paradoxes of time Travel' Richard Taylor, 'Freedom, Determinism and Fate' Option 2 b): Some hold that free will is (a) not only incompatible with determinism but (b) also incompatible with indeterminism. Explain this objection and explain how Kane addresses (b). Evaluate Kane's position. Do you think his view allows for people to have genuine control over and to be genuinely responsible for their actions? Give your own examples that help illustrate/justify your points. Required reading: Kane, ‘Libertarianism’

  11. Soft Determinsim vs Compatibilism “There are compatibilists who are agnostic about the truth or falsity of determinism, so a compatibilist need not be a soft determinist (someone who believes that it is in fact the case that determinism is true and we have free will). But all compatibilists believe that it is at least possible that determinism is true and we have free will. So all compatibilists are committed to the claim that there are deterministic worlds that are free will worlds.” Kadri Vihvelin, “Arguments for Incompatibilism http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/compatibilism/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/incompatibilism-arguments/ See also https://yandoo.wordpress.com/2013/10/25/determinism-free-will-and-compatibilism/

  12. Richard Taylor writes: A determinist is simply, if he is consistent, a fatalist about everything; or at least, he should be. For the essential idea that a man would be expressing by saying that his attitude was one of fatalism with respect to this or that event—his own death, for instance—is that it is not up to him whether, or when or where this event will occur, that it is not within his control. But the theory of determinism, as we have seen, once it is clearly spelled out and not hedged about with unresolved “ifs”, entails that this is true of everything that ever happens, that it is never really up to any man what he does or what he becomes, and that nothing ever can happen, except what does in fact happen. He goes on to say that fatalism should lead to resignation: A fatalist is best thought of, quite simply, as someone who thinks he cannot do anything about the future. He think it is not up to him what will happen next year, tomorrow, or the very next moment. He thinks that even his own behaviour is not in the least within his power, any more than the motion of distant heavenly bodies, the events of remote history, or the political developments in faraway countries. He supposes, accordingly, that it is pointless for him to deliberate about anything, for aman deliberates only about those future things he believes to be within his power to do and forego. Taylor, Richard, Metaphysics, 1974 (Englewood Cliffs NJ: Prentice Hall).

  13. http://andrewmbailey.com/pvi/How_to_Think_About_Free_Will.pdfhttp://andrewmbailey.com/pvi/How_to_Think_About_Free_Will.pdf “How to Think about the Problem of Free Will” by Peter van Inwagen, Journal of Ethics, (2008), 12:327–341 http://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/philosophers/lewis/Are_we_free_to_break_laws.pdf ”Are we free to break the laws?” David Lewis, Theora 47, (1981), pp 112-21 TIP: be clear about your terminology – eg say exactly what you define free will, determinism and compatibilism to be.

  14. 3. Thinking Machines On the question whether machines can think, Descartes and Turing are in strong disagreement. Evaluate the arguments on either side. Does Searle's 'Chinese Room' argument help resolve the debate? Required reading: Alan Turing, 'Computing Machinery and Intelligence' John Searle, 'Minds, Brains and Programs' (Quotes from Descartes can be found in the Notes to Part 3 of the Study Guide.) How does Descartes’ argue against thinking machines? How does Turing’s argue for thinking machines? How does Searle argue against thinking machines? In each case ask: What is the claim? What is the argument? TIP Don’t confuse thinking, intelligence and consciousness (or syntax, semantics, understanding and intentionality).

  15. 4. The Self If you teletransport to another planet, we might wonder whether the resulting individual is you---whether you've really survived. Parfit argues that identity is not what matters when we consider our futures in such cases. How does he reach this conclusion by considering the problem of fission? Is this a good argument? Is there more reason to think that identity does matter to survival? (Here you might focus more on Williams or Lewis, rather than discussing them both in detail.) Required reading: Derek Parfit, 'Personal Identity' Bernard Williams, 'The Self and the Future' David Lewis, 'Survival and Identity’ TIP: Be clear what Parfit claims and how he argues for his claims. Be clear what Williams or Lewis claim and how it challenges Parfit’s claim. Remain focussed on whether it is you who is teletransported.

  16. What makes someone the same person over time? Locke: Memory; Reid: Persons are continuing entities; Butler: Memory presupposes personal identity, because there needs to be a consciousness to do the remembering; Parfit: Not identity, survival; Williams: Not psychological survival, bodily survival; Lewis: Connected temporal-person-stages.

  17. Teleportation Imagine a teleport machine that works as follows. It scans and records everything about your body, down to the atomic level. That information is then sent to the receiving teleport machine, which reconstructs your body exactly from a stock pile of raw material. The scanning process destroys all the original atoms of your body. Question: Is this really a way to travel? Would you use it? Is the person who arrives at the destination you?

  18. Teleportation

  19. Teleportation Imagine the machine breaks down. An exact duplicate of you is created at the destination, but the original you is not destroyed. Or what if two copies of you were created at the other end? Again, the person / people at the other end are psychologically continuous with you, But are they really you? Most people answer no – this kind of machine is not a way to travel. It just creates a duplicate of you (like an identical twin). Perhaps it is bodily continuity that really matter then, rather than psychological continuity. (Williams)

  20. Parfit’s argument (1) Identity is a one-one relation that does not admit of degrees. (2) Psychological continuity need not be one-one and can come in degrees. (Fission and fusion cases) (3) What matters in survival is psychological continuity (whether your mental life continues on) Therefore: (C) What matters in survival is not identity. Lewis wants to accept all three premises, but reject the conclusion.

  21. Temporal stages Lewis makes use of the idea that a person is a unified whole consisting of temporal stages or temporal parts. Think of a person as a four-dimensional object which is stretched out in time. At any particular time, only the temporal parts are present, never the whole person. This conception of identity through time should be distinguished from an endurantist conception, according to which the whole person is present at all the times that it exists.

  22. Tensed Identity “You may feel certain that you count persons by identity and not tensed identity. But how can you be sure? Normal cases provide no evidence…. The problem cases provide no very solid evidence either. They are problem cases just because we cannot consistently say quite all the things we feel inclined to, We must strike the best compromise among our conflicting opinions. Something must give way: and why not the opinion that of course we count by identity, if that is what can be sacrificed with the least total damage?” Lewis, ‘Survival and Identity’, p. 227

  23. 5. Knowledge Gettier raises some serious challenges for the traditional account of knowledge. Nozick develops his tracking account in part to answer the problems identified by Gettier. After explaining both Gettier's challenge and Nozick's proposal, evaluate the strength of Nozick's proposal as a response to Gettier's challenge. Required reading: Edmund Gettier, 'Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?' Robert Nozick, 'Knowledge and Skepticism'

  24. From Sample Exam - now on Moodle Part 5 (Knowledge): 13. What is the traditional analysis of knowledge? Explain it and then provide a Gettierstyle counterexample to it—either one of Gettier’s own counterexamples, one discussed in the literature, or one you have made up yourself (doing the latter of course is most impressive). Explain exactly how the counterexample is meant to work. 14. How does Nozick try to use his tracking theory to object to the “closure argument” used by skeptics who maintain we cannot know if there is an external world? On which this argument rests? (Note: If you use abbreviations or formal symbols, be sure to say what they represent.) 15. What is Cartesian skepticism? And how does Descartes’ line of reasoning support it?

  25. From Sample Exam - now on Moodle Part 5 (Knowledge): 13. What is the traditional analysis of knowledge? Explain it and then provide a Gettierstyle counterexample to it—either one of Gettier’s own counterexamples, one discussed in the literature, or one you have made up yourself (doing the latter of course is most impressive). Explain exactly how the counterexample is meant to work. 14. How does Nozick try to use his tracking theory to object to the “closure argument” used by skeptics who maintain we cannot know if there is an external world? On which this argument rests? (Note: If you use abbreviations or formal symbols, be sure to say what they represent.) 15. What is Cartesian skepticism? And how does Descartes’ line of reasoning support it?

  26. Essay Topics Write on one of the following topics. AT4 Essay - Mon Oct 12th, 10am - @1250 words – 30% 5. Knowledge Gettier raises some serious challenges for the traditional account of knowledge. Nozick develops his tracking account in part to answer the problems identified by Gettier. After explaining both Gettier's challenge and Nozick's proposal, evaluate the strength of Nozick's proposal as a response to Gettier's challenge. Required reading: Edmund Gettier, 'Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?' Robert Nozick, 'Knowledge and Skepticism'

  27. 1. Knowledge as Justified True Belief There are three components to the traditional (“tripartite”) analysis of knowledge. According to this analysis, justified, true belief is necessary and sufficient for knowledge. The Tripartite Analysis of Knowledge:
S knows that p iff p is true; S believes that p; S is justified in believing that p. The tripartite analysis of knowledge is often abbreviated as the “JTB” analysis, for “justified true belief”. From http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/index.html

  28. A Counterexample? Stubborn Evolutionist: Henry has been exposed to a number of rationally compelling arguments for the theory of evolution. Despite understanding these arguments, Henry refuses to accept [evolution], through sheer stubbornness. One day, Henry’s tarot card reader tells him that, based on a recent tarot reading, she has determined that the theory of evolution is true. Henry then finally accepts evolution on the basis of the tarot reading. QUESTION: Does Harry know that evolution is true? Derelict Juror: Imagine two jurors, Jenna and Natilie, deliberating about the case of Mr. Mansour. Both jurors have paid close attention throughout the trial. As a result, both have good reason to believe that Mansour is guilty. Each juror goes on to form the belief that Mansour is guilty, which he in fact is. Natilie believes he’s guilty because of the evidence presented during the trial. Jenna believes he’s guilty because he looks suspicious. QUESTION: Does Jenna know that Mansour is guilty?

  29. The Basing Demand General Issue: • S can have terrific evidence to think P true. • S can believe P is true. • But S can fail to believe P because of the evidence. = S can fail to base her belief in P on the evidence. = S can believe P for obviously irrelevant reasons. The Basing Demand: In order to knowP one must have a justified beliefin P. In order to have a justified belief one must base that belief on good reasons.

  30. Epistemic Luck (Russell) Alice sees a clock that reads two o’clock, and believes that the time is two o’clock. It is in fact two o'clock. There's a problem, however: unknown to Alice, the clock she’s looking at stopped twelve hours ago. Alice thus has an accidentally true, justified belief. Russell

  31. 3. The Gettier Problem In his short 1963 paper, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?”, Edmund Gettier presented two effective counterexamples to the JTB analysis (Gettier 1963). One of these goes as follows. Suppose Smith has good evidence for the false proposition (1)Jones owns a Ford. Suppose further Smith infers from (1) the following three disjunctions: (2)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Boston. (3)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona. (4)Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Brest-Litovsk. Since (1) entails each of the propositions (2) through (4), and since Smith recognizes these entailments, his beliefs in propositions (2)–(4) are justified. Now suppose that, by sheer coincidence, Brown is indeed in Barcelona. Given these assumptions, we may say that Smith, when he believes (3), holds a justified true belief. However, is Smith's belief an instance of knowledge? Intuitively, Smith's belief cannot be knowledge; it is merely lucky that it is true.

  32. In the first example, Gettier supposes that two people, Smith and Jones, have applied for a job. We suppose that Smith has a justified belief that Jones will get the job. The evidence for it is high enough that Smith justifiably believes it, “might be that the president of the company assured him that Jones would in the end be selected” Smith also believes (and indeed, knows) that Jones has ten coins in his pocket, which is true and was demonstrated to him, possibly by Jones counting them himself. From this he believes the logical conseqence of these beliefs, that “the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket”¹ It turns out that Smith was wrong, and that, for some unforseeable reason, it turns out that Smith gets the job, and Jones does not. It also turns out that Smith has ten coins in his pocket, though he didn't realize it. The question is, was Smith's belief that “the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket” knowledge?

  33. Smith has very strong evidence to believe that his friend, Jones owns a Ford. Gettier writes: “Jones has at all times in the past within Smith's memory owned a car, and always a Ford, and that Jones has just offered Smith a ride while driving a Ford”¹ Suppose that Smith also knows someone named Brown, but he has no idea where Brown is. From this he forms several disjunctions, one of which is “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona”. This is a justifiable thing to do, given the justifiable belief that Jones owns a Ford. Suppose that, despite all of his evidence, Smith is wrong, and it turns out that Jones does not own a Ford. Perhaps he was borrowing a friend's car, or owned a Ford but has since sold it. In any case, Smith's belief that Jones owns a Ford is false. However, it turns out, by sheer coincidence, that Brown is, in fact, in Barcelona. Surely, one would not claim that Brown knew the proposition “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona”, since he had no idea where Brown was, and Jones does not own a Ford. He formed other false disjunctions the same way, believing also that “Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Boston” was equally true.

  34. Gettier and Propositional Knowledge Gettier argues that one could have a true justified belief which is not knowledge in a situation in which one reasons from some already justified beliefs to a new belief that, as it happens, is coincidentally true. Since it would then be a matter of coincidence that one’s belief was correct, it would not count as knowledge, even though it was a justified belief because it was knowingly inferred from already justified beliefs.

  35. Most epistemologists have accepted Gettier's argument, taking it to show that the three conditions of the JTB account—truth, belief, and justification—are not in general sufficient for knowledge. How must the analysis of knowledge be modified to make it immune to cases like the one we just considered? This is what is commonly referred to as the “Gettier problem”. Above, we noted that one role of the justification is to rule out lucky guesses as cases of knowledge. A lesson of the Gettier problem is that it appears that even true beliefs that are justified can nevertheless be epistemically lucky in a way inconsistent with knowledge. Epistemologists who think that the JTB approach is basically on the right track must choose between two different strategies for solving the Gettier problem From http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/index.html

  36. Structure of the Counterexample Reminder:Traditional account says JTB is necessary & sufficient for knowledge. Question: What does this counterexample teach us about the JTB account of knowledge? JTB is… (a) Not necessary for knowledge. (b) Not sufficient for knowledge. (c) Neither necessary nor sufficient for knowledge. Structure of the Counterexample: S has JTB But: S doesn’t know that p So: JTB is insufficient for knowledge How to Proceed: S knows that p iffJTB + ? Any guesses as to what should be added?

  37. Structure of Gettier counterexamples Both of Gettier's counterexamples essentially follow the same general form: Smith justifiably believes that P. P is false. Smith correctly infers that if P is true, then Q is true. So, Smith believes Q, justifiably. Q is true, but not because of P. So, Smith has a justified true belief that Q. In these examples, and all true Gettier-style examples, the flaw arises from forming an inference based on a false premise, though there is sufficient evidence to believe that premise is true.

  38. Nozick (sensitivity conditions) • S knows that p iff: • p is true. • S believes p. • If p were false, S would not believe p. • If p were true, S would believe p. • Which is to say:- • s knows that p when the following conditions hold • p is true • s believes p • If p were the case then s would believe p • If p were not the case then s would not believe it

  39. The Sheep Case (NTA): S knows that p only iff: • p is true. • S believes p. • If p were not true, then S would not believe p. • … Question:Is condition 3 satisfied in the Sheep Case? That is, is the following true: (A) If there were no sheep in the field, S would not believe that there are sheep in the field. NO! I.e., S would still believe it. • So condition 3 is not satisfied. • So according to Nozick’s theory, one does not know that there is a sheep in the field. This is exactly the conclusion we want.

  40. From Sample Exam What do the Gettier examples show? (A) That knowledge is justified true belief. (B) That having a justified, true belief is sufficient for knowledge. (C) That having a justified, true belief is necessary for knowledge. (D) None of the above.

More Related