1 / 33

BAMS 517 – 2010 Decision Analysis -III Utility

BAMS 517 – 2010 Decision Analysis -III Utility. Martin L. Puterman UBC Sauder School of Business Winter Term 2 2010 Version January 13, 2010. A curious gamble. Gamble A; Flip a coin- Heads win $1; Tails lose $1 Gamble B; Flip a coin- Heads win $1 million; Tails lose $1 million

eurydice
Download Presentation

BAMS 517 – 2010 Decision Analysis -III Utility

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. BAMS 517 – 2010Decision Analysis -IIIUtility Martin L. Puterman UBC Sauder School of Business Winter Term 2 2010 Version January 13, 2010

  2. A curious gamble • Gamble A; Flip a coin- Heads win $1; Tails lose $1 • Gamble B; Flip a coin- Heads win $1 million; Tails lose $1 million • The expected value for each is $0. • Which would you choose?

  3. Another curious gamble • Consider the following game; flip a coin until you get a head. • Payoff – head the first time $2, head the second time $4, head the third time $8, … • What is the expected value of this game? • This is called the St. Petersburg Paradox • The paradox is named from Daniel Bernoulli's presentation of the problem and his solution, published in 1738 in the Commentaries of the Imperial Academy of Science of Saint Petersburg. However, the problem was invented by Daniel's cousin Nicolas Bernoulli who first stated it in a letter to Pierre Raymond de Montmort of 9 September 1713.  • Of it, Daniel Bernoulli said “The determination of the value of an item must not be based on the price, but rather on the utility it yields…. There is no doubt that a gain of one thousand ducats is more significant to the pauper than to a rich man though both gain the same amount.” • Gabriel Cramer, a Swiss Mathematician said; “mathematicians estimate money in proportion to its quantity, and men of good sense in proportion to the usage that they may make of it”.

  4. Basic idea • To avoid these situations we can work backwards through a decision tree by replacing each gamble by our personal assessment of its value • Shortcomings of this approach • It is tedious • May not be accurate • May be inconsistent • Sometimes difficult; especially if gamble has many possible outcomes. • Another approach - replace outcomes by there utility.

  5. When is utility useful? • Monetary outcomes • To systematically incorporate personal attitudes towards consequences of decisions and risk • Large losses may be catastrophic • To evaluate complex gambles systematically • Win $207 with probability .17 and lose $114 with probability .83. • To evaluate decisions involving non-monetary outcomes • Health outcomes – years of life vs. quality • To evaluate decisions with multiple dimensions to outcomes • Wealth, happiness, …

  6. What is utility? Some preliminary definitions Let {x, y, z, w} be possible outcomes of a decision problem. Then • x > y means "x is preferred to y" (also known as strict preference) • x ~ y means "x is viewed indifferently relative to y" • x >~ y means "x is either preferred or viewed indifferently relative to y" (also known as weak preference) • (x,p,y) means a gamble (an uncertain outcome, or a lottery) in which outcome x will be received with probability p, and outcome y will be received with probability 1-p. Example: x is $150, y is a ticket to a Canucks game; z is a 50-50 lottery which either wins $200 or a 20 year old PC and w is one week of good health

  7. What is utility? Consistency Axioms for outcomes and preferences For any outcomes x,y,z,w and numbers p,q between 0 and 1 the following hold: 1. Weak ordering. (a) x >~ x. (Reflexivity) (b) x >~ y or y >~ x. (Connectivity) (c) x >~ y and y >~ z imply x >~ z. (Transitivity) 2. Reducibility. ((x,p,y),q,y) ~ (x,pq,y). 3. Independence. If (x,p,z) ~ (y,p,z), then (x,p,w) ~ (y,p,w). 4. Betweenness. If x > y, then x > (x,p,y) > y. 5. Solvability. If x > y > z, then there exists p such that y ~ (x,p,z). Example: x is $150, y is a ticket to a Canucks playoff game, z is a 50-50 lottery which either wins $200 or a 20 year old PC, and w is one week of good health

  8. What is utility? A key theoretical result and interpretation • Theorem: (J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 1944 (Also attributable to Ramsay (1931)) If Axioms 1-5 are satisfied for all outcomes, then there exists a real-valued utility function u(s) defined on outcomes, with the properties that: • x > y if and only if u(x) > u(y), and x ~ y if and only if u(x) = u(y); • u(x,p,y) = pu(x)+(1-p)u(y); • u is unique up to order preserving affine transformations; that is, if v is any other function satisfying 1. and 2. then there exist real numbers b, and a>0, such that v(x) = au(x)+b. • This means that if we believe the consistency axioms: • There is a function u(s) that captures our preferences for outcomes; the higher the utility the more we prefer the outcome. • The utility of a lottery is the expected utility. • The relative difference between outcomes measures our relative preference for outcomes • The consequence of all this is that in a decision problem • We value all outcomes by their utility • We replace a lottery by its expected utility • We choose decisions which maximize utility

  9. Using Utility: U(x) = ((x+2000)/10000).5 Utility .8367 5000 .5 Choice A .5 -1000 .3163 Choice B .5916 1500 Choice A has EMV = $2000 and Expected Utility = .5764; so under EMV you prefer A and under Expected Utility you prefer B. At what value for Choice B would you be indifferent? 1322.87 which is the certainty equivalent of A

  10. Alberta Exploration Revisited • Suppose we revisit Alberta Exploration but use expected utility instead of expected monetary value as our optimality criterion • How might our utility change. • For simplicity we assume an exponential utility function u(x) = xa normalized so that 0 ≤ u(x) ≤ 1. • That is u(x) = ((x-b)/c)a • See Alberta Utility

  11. St. Petersburg Paradox Revisited • Bernoulli suggest used a utility function u(x) =ln(x) • Thus the value of receiving 2n is ln(2n) = nln(2) so that the E(u(X))= 2ln(2) = 1.3863 • Hence the certainty equivalent of this gamble would be e1.3863 = 4.

  12. Assessing a decision maker’s utility Best outcome p Choice A 1-p Worst outcome Choice B Specified intermediate outcome

  13. Assessing a decision maker’s utility • We can use a similar approach to that used for assessing probabilities. • Take a reference lottery for which the utility of the two outcomes are known and the probability of receiving the better one is p. • We start by assigning utility of 1 to best outcome B and 0 to worst outcome W. • We compare it to a decision with no randomness and a fixed payoff C. • Two approaches; • Fix p and vary C • Fix C and vary p (using spinner) • In the first case we find the value C that has utility p • In the second case we find the utility p of receiving C for sure. • Which is easier?

  14. Assessing a decision maker’s utility • Iterative approach; • Set p = .5 and find C1 so that u(C1)=.5 • Now consider a 50-50 lottery between C1 and B. Assign utility .75 to the equivalent value C2. • Now consider a 50-50 lottery between C1 and W. Assign utility .25 to the equivalent value C3. • Continue this process • Check for consistency and whether it agrees with our attitude towards risk. • Plot and smooth utility curve. • Considerable behavioral research on doing this to avoid bias • Exercise • Find your utility curve for a decision problem with outcomes ranging from -5000 to 20000.

  15. Another interpretation of utility • Assume u(s) is normalized so it’s value falls between 0 and 1. • Then suppose we have a fixed outcome with utility q. • Then this fixed outcomes is equivalent to a lottery with outcomes B with probability q and w with probability 1-q. • Thus we can reduce a decision problem to one in which every endpoint is a lottery between B and W. • Of course our preference is for lotteries with higher probabilities of receiving B. • Thus we can think of the utility as the probability of receiving the best outcome.

  16. Shape of Utility Functions • A utility function u(•) is concave if for any a satisfying 0  a  1 u(ax + (1-a)y)  au(x) + (1-a) u(y) for any x and y in S. • A twice differentiable concave utility function has a non-positive second derivative (u’’ ≤ 0) • Examples • u(x) =ln(x) • u(x) = √x • u(x) = 1-e-ax • An individual who possesses a strictly concave utility function is said to be risk averse. • By strictly concave , I mean it is not linear on any intervals. • A key property of a strictly concave utility function is decreasing marginal utility. That means as x increases the slope or value of an additional unit, u`(x), decreases. • An individual with a linear utility function is said to be risk neutral. • This is appropriate when you • Repeat the gamble many times • Consequences are small (utility curve is approximately linear over small increments) • An individual with a convex utility function is risk seeking. • Example u(x) = x2 • Comments • Often we normalize the utility function so that its maximum value is 1 and its minimum value is 0. • In decision problems we often define our utility for our total wealth, not the just the outcome of the gamble.

  17. Decreasing marginal utility • It is not always reasonable to assume that you will value an additional $100 equally regardless of how much money you already have • You would probably value an extra $100 less if you were very wealthy than if you were very poor • This phenomenon of valuing an additional dollar less, the more money you already have, is known as decreasing marginal utility • Decreasing marginal utility implies that the utility function has a concave shape – see graph • The horizontal lines in the graph show the additional (marginal) utility of each additional $20 • Note that the derivative of u is decreasing as the monetary value increases • Would this argument apply to an extra day of life? u(80) u(60) u(40) u(20)

  18. Risk-aversion: a graphical view • Consider the following options: • A chance pof $50 and (1-p) of $10 • A sure outcome of $[50p + 10(1-p)] • Line AB represents the expected utility of option 1 for any value of p • Note this line lies under the curve • It’s equation is pu(50)+(1-p)u(10) • For p = 0.5, the expected monetary value of either option is $30 • The blue line represents the expected utility of option 1 • The red line to point C represents the utility of option 2 • The sure outcome will have a higher expected value whenever the decision maker is risk averse. u(50) C u(10)

  19. Certainty equivalence of gambles • Consider now a gamble (decision) that can either result in having a dollars with probability p, or to b dollars with probability 1–p, where a > b • A is the expected utility of the gamble • C is a dollar value such that you would be indifferent between having $C for certain and accepting the gamble • The utility of C for certain is equal to the expected utility of the gamble • u(C) = pu(a) +(1-p)u(b) • The value C is called the certainty equivalent value of the gamble • C = u-1(A) • Certainty equivalent = inverse of u applied to expected utility of gamble • B = pa+(1-p)b is the expected monetary outcome of the gamble which exceeds C. • Why? A C B a b

  20. An important decision problem; Insurance • Suppose you want to buy insurance against the theft of your car, which you value at $20,000. You currently have $40,000 in total assets • You assess the likelihood of your car being stolen in the next year at 0.5% • If you don’t buy insurance, you will have $40,000 with 99.5% probability, and $20,000 with probability 0.5% The expected monetary outcome is therefore .995($40,000)+.005($20,000) = $39,900 • If you buy insurance at a price c, then you will have $40,000 – c, regardless of whether your car is stolen or not • You would buy insurance at price c if u(40,000 – c) > 0.995u(40,000) + .005u(20,000) • If you are risk-neutral, you would be willing to spend up to $40,000 – $39,900 = $100 on car insurance • If you are risk-averse, would you be willing to spend more or less than $100?

  21. Insurance • We plot the insurance-buying problem in the graph at right, assuming risk-aversion (not to scale) • B represents the expected monetary value of not buying insurance = $39,900 • A represents the expected utility of the decision not to buy insurance = 0.995u(40,000) + .005u(20,000) • C represents the monetary value at which u(C) = A (certainty equivalence) • You would pay up to $40,000 – C for insurance with this utility fn. • You would pay up to $40,000 – B if you were risk neutral • If you are risk-averse, you would be willing to pay more than the expected value for insurance • Why would anyone sell you insurance? A C B $40K $20K

  22. Risk premiums • The previous examples show that for a risk-averse decision-maker, the value of a gamble (its certainty equivalent) will be less than its ‘fair value’ (expected monetary outcome) • This follows from the concavity of the utility function • Risk-averse people would refuse a ‘fair’ bet • The difference between the ‘fair value’ and the certain equivalence value of the gamble (between points B and C in the previous graphs) is known as the risk premium • If the risk premium is negative you would be risk seeking • If this holds for all outcomes you would have a convex utility function. • Recall roulette and horse race betting are “unfair games” and have negative risk premiums • Note people may have a utility function that is risk seeking for gambles with positive payoffs and risk averse for negative consequences. • What would such a utility function look like?

  23. Risk premiums • The size of the risk premium can be used to measure the degree of risk-aversion to a particular gamble • Consider the two utility curves pictured at left. The red curve is ‘more concave’ in the region between the two outcomes and corresponds to a more risk-averse decision maker • The point D is the certainty-equivalent value for this more risk-averse decision-maker • The point C is the certainty-equivalent for the less risk averse decision maker • The risk premium B – D is greater than B-C for the risk averse decision maker. A D C B $b $a (Note: The two utility curves coincide at the points a and b in this graph only for convenience of exposition.)

  24. Measuring risk aversion We say that utility curve u is more risk averse than utility curve v if for all outcomes x and y and every lottery (x,p,y) the certain-equivalent of u is less than certain-equivalent of v. Theorem (Pratt) This is true if and only if –u’’(x)/u’(x) > -v’’(x)/v’(x) for all outcomes v. Proof The quantity –u’’(x)/u’(x) is called the Arrow-Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion

  25. The value of a gamble • Suppose that your utility function for total wealth $x is u(x) = x1/2 • For simplicity, we won’t bother here to normalize the utilities between 0 and 1 • Consider a gamble that pays $5000 with probability 0.5 and -$5000 with probability 0.5 (i.e., you have to pay $5000 if you lose) • The following table shows that your risk premium depends on your wealth: • Thus with this utility function, the more money you already have, the less money you would require in compensation for accepting the gamble

  26. The value of a gamble • The fact that the risk premium can vary with initial wealth means that we can’t consider the value of a gamble in isolation from our total wealth • It may be inconvenient if we have to constantly have to refer to our current level of wealth in order to judge the value of a gamble • There are certain utility functions, however, for which the value of a gamble can be judged apart from total wealth • For example, consider the utility function u(x) = 1 – exp(-x/10000). The following table lists the risk premiums for each:

  27. Utility functions with the delta property • Utility functions for which the risk premium of a gamble does not depend on the initial level of wealth are said to have the delta property • It can be shown that all such utility functions are either of the form (up to a linear scaling) u(x) = x, or u(x) = 1 – exp(-cx), for some c > 0 • The parameter c is known as the risk aversion constant: the higher the value of c, the more risk-averse one is (see graph at right) • Risk-neutral utility functions have the delta property • Is this a desirable property of a utility function? more risk-averse less risk-averse

  28. Example: the jellybean game • Suppose there are 50% red jellybeans in a jar, and your utility function for total wealth $x is u(x) = 1 – exp(-x/10). You win $10 if you draw a red jellybean and $0 otherwise • The fair value of this game is $5 – if you were risk-neutral, you would pay up to this amount to play the game • We now compute the certain equivalent of the game. Because the utility function has the delta property, you can ignore total wealth – just assume x = 0. • Expected utility is then U = .5(1 – e-1) + .5(1 – e0) = .316 • The certain equivalent is then u-1(.316) = -10•ln(1 - .316) = 3.80 • You would pay up to $3.80 to play the game (regardless of your current wealth) • Using utilities that have the delta property is convenient. You can use such a utility function if you assume that your aversion to risk is constant, regardless of your current wealth

  29. More on risk aversion • The linear (risk-neutral) and exponential utility functions we have discussed so far are convenient functions to use • Both of these functions presume that your level of risk aversion is constant, regardless of your level of wealth • This is what it means to have the delta-property • Another measure of the risk-aversion associated with a utility function u(•) at a level of wealth x is the value r(x) = –u’’(x) / u’(x). • For linear utility functions, r(x) = 0. • For u(x) = a – bexp(-kx), r(x) = k • Constant risk-aversion is not always be a reasonable assumption – as you grow richer, you may become more tolerant of risk – your risk-aversion should decrease • Other commonly used utility functions are of the form u(x) = xk, for 0 < k< 1 or u(x)=ln(x) • The risk-aversion associated with these utility functions decreases as wealth grows • For example for u(x) = ln(x), r(x) = 1/x. • Ultimately, for any major decision, you will have to think hard about how much you value the outcomes – you don’t want to assume a utility function merely because it has a convenient form

  30. Expected value of perfect information under utility • If your utility function has the delta property, then the difference in the certain equivalents of these decisions represents the amount that you should be willing to pay to acquire information • If you are risk-neutral, then this is simply the difference in the expected monetary value of the two decisions • If your utility function does not have the delta property, then computing how much you should be willing to pay to acquire information is more difficult. The following approach will work. • Suppose you must pay x for perfect information. • If you pay x, then each endpoint on the PI decision tree is reduced by x. • Then vary x so that the utility of the perfect information decision tree equals that of the perfect information decision tree.

  31. Buying vs. selling • Suppose there is a lottery such that with probability .5 you get 1000 and with probability .5 you lose 200. • Would you pay the same price to buy it as you would to sell it? • Yes, if you use expected value • Maybe, if you are risk averse • Yes if your utility has the delta property • No, otherwise • What if you are risk seeking?

  32. Summary so far • Utility provides a way of valuing outcomes that takes your risk attitude into account. • To use it in the context of decision analysis replace all endpoints by their utilities and do backward induction as in the expected value case. • Utility functions differ between decision makers. • You can assess a decision maker’s utility function by asking him/her to evaluate gambles • The certainty equivalent gives the monetary value of a decision problem. • For risk averse decision makers, the utility function is concave and the risk premium is positive. • But behavioral studies suggest that utility theory might not describe how people really behave. • We will not cover assessing multi-attribute utilities or utilities for health outcomes.

More Related