1 / 13

Philosophy 220

Philosophy 220. The Death Penalty: Theories of Punishment, Nathanson. Capital Punishment and the Law. The 8 th amendment to the Constitution prohibits the infliction of 'cruel and unusual' punishment. If capital punishment is a cruel and unusual punishment, then it is unconstitutional.

dewei
Download Presentation

Philosophy 220

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Philosophy 220 The Death Penalty: Theories of Punishment, Nathanson

  2. Capital Punishment and the Law • The 8th amendment to the Constitution prohibits the infliction of 'cruel and unusual' punishment. If capital punishment is a cruel and unusual punishment, then it is unconstitutional. • In Furman v. Georgia (1972), the Supreme Court ruled that the death penalty was cruel and unusual as then administered. They explicitly did not go so far as to insist that the death penalty was unconstitutional by its very nature. • In Gregg v. Georgia (1976), the court found that the DP was not unconstitutional when imposed at the discretion of a jury for the crime of murder, so long as appropriate safeguards are in place to protect from arbitrary or capricious decisions. • 37 states now have statutes authorizing capital punishment with the Gregg principles in place. Since 1976, 1,178 people have been executed under this system.

  3. The Moral Issue • Of course, for us the legal status of the death penalty is less significant than its moral status. • That this a live and important concern is amply testified to by the statistics on public opinion Timmons summarizes on p. 359. • As he states it, the issue can be summarized by two questions: • Is the death penalty ever a [morally] permissible form of punishment (as opposed to a legally permissible form)? • If it is, why is it?

  4. Untangling Morality and the Law • The DP is a complicated issue in part because though our primary concerns are moral and theoretical, any system of capital punishment is a legal system. • In other words, we are asking moral questions about the status of a legal system, more specifically a system of punishment.

  5. A Moral Justification for Punishment • Most people would agree that not all instances or forms of punishment are morally acceptable. • A parent may choose to chain their child to her bed for back talking, but most of us would insist that this is not an appropriate punishment. • Timmons provides us with a list of conditions that help us understand the nature of legal punishment (360). • The primary moral concern with any such system is the strong presumption against harming people (The Harm Principle: Do no harm).

  6. Retributivism and Punishment • Responding to the need for a moral justification of punishment requires providing an answer to the two questions highlighted on the third slide. • One popular approach to the question is the Retributive Theory, which focuses our attention on the actions of the wrong doer. • In response to the first question, retributivism argues that punishment is justified because the wrong doer deserves it. • In response to the second question, retributivism specifies a concept of fitness: the punishment should fit the crime.

  7. Retributivism and the Death Penalty • Though retributivism provides a straightforward justification for punishment in general, the question of the death penalty is more complicated. • The sticking point is the notion of fit. • Proponents of DP (retentionists) typically interpret fitness along the lines of Lex Talonis(essentially, “an eye for an eye). • Opponents (abolitionists) argue instead for a principle of proportionality: a punishment is justified if it is proportional to the crime.

  8. Consequentialism and Punishment • Another approach adopts a consequentialist standpoint, justifying punishment on the grounds that the consequences of punishment have greater value than other possible approaches. • Consequentialists answer the first question by insisting that punishment is only justified when in fact its consequences are in fact (or are likely to be) of higher value than the alternatives. • They answer the second question in any specific instance with a calculation that demonstrates the value consequences.

  9. Consequentialism and DP • Unlike with retributivism, there are no special considerations that develop when consequentialism is applied to DP. • There are however some specific positive and negative utility considerations that have to be kept in mind. • On the positive side, retentionists point to possible deterrent effects of DP as well as the obvious fact that execution prevents a murderer from killing again. • On the negative side, abolitionists point to the possibility of executing the innocent by mistake, to the costs of administering DP (higher even then life imprisonment) and what is known as the coarsening effect (following an execution, the rate of murder by strangers actually increases for a time).

  10. Nathanson ”An Eye for an Eye?" • Nathanson offers a critique of retributivism of both the Lex Talonis (equality) and proportional sort. • He completes his case by arguing that abolition would have the important symbolic significance of signaling that our society is committed to the absolute dignity of human life in every person.

  11. The Problem with Equality (Lex Talonis) Retributivism. • Nathanson argues that equality is not an adequate criterion for determining punishment in general. • It recommends punishments for certain crimes that are not morally acceptable. If a crime is barbaric and inhumane, then Lex Talonis would require us to act barbarously and inhumanely (ex. rape a rapist). • Can't tell us how to punish many crimes. E.g. Computer piracy, or plagiarism. • If it’s not adequate in general, then it is obviously not adequate for DP. • A possible response is to seek a non-literal form of equality retributivism. Nathanson responds by noting that there is still the barbarity problem. Also, we run into the problem of how to accurately judge equivalence, either in the case of abstract crimes or in the case of varying resistances to suffering.

  12. Problems with Proportional Retributivism • This theory is usually advanced in terms of a proportional ranking of punishments and crimes. Such a strategy avoids the major flaws of equality retributivism. • One problem from the standpoint of the retentionist is that it doesn't necessitate that murder should be punished with death, just with the most severe punishment in the scale. • A practical problem is that in and of itself it provides no resources with deciding the appropriateness/effectiveness of punishments. Needs to be supplemented by empirical data. • According to Nathanson, this form of retributivism does have an important role to play in our judicial system, but it doesn’t justify DP.

  13. Nathanson as an Abolitionist • In addition to criticizing retributive justifications for DP, Nathanson advances interesting abolitionist arguments. • The first highlights that respect for human dignity is a central element of our social structure. Nathanson argues that the DP undermines this respect to the extent that it says that some people have no value. We cannot consistently say that all people are valued and that some are not. • The second emphasizes the symbolic significance. Nathanson argues that abolishing the DP would provide an example of proper behavior, saying that we will not act with the same inhumanity that the murderer did.

More Related