1 / 20

Linguistic Theory

Linguistic Theory. Lecture 7 About Nothing. Nothing in grammar. Language often contains irregular paradigms where one or more expected forms are absent E.g. English present tense verb agreement

alagan
Download Presentation

Linguistic Theory

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Linguistic Theory Lecture 7 About Nothing

  2. Nothing in grammar • Language often contains irregular paradigms where one or more expected forms are absent • E.g. English present tense verb agreement • We see from the paradigm for be that number and person play a role in determining the form of the verb in the present tense:

  3. But other verbs do not show the same pattern • The only form which shows any agreement is the 3rd person singular • Two choices: • Assume that there is no verbal agreement except for 3rd person singular and for 1st, 2nd and 3rd person singular with the verb be • Assume that there is a complete set of verbal agreements, only most of them are realised by a null morpheme • The second choice is the one usually made as it makes the system more regular

  4. Other kinds of nothing • Ellipsis • She wanted to watch the TV, but I didn’t • (want to watch the TV) • * (take any notice) • There is a difference: • null morpheme = absent at the phonological level • elliptical material = present at the semantic level

  5. Nothing in the 1960s • One possible way to treat ellipsis is as a deletion: • John drank beer and Bill wine • John drank beer and Bill drank wine • Deletions are recoverable: • * John drank beer and Bill biscuits • John drank beer and Bill ate biscuits • This shows that ‘recoverability’ is a limited notion: • Recoverable from syntactic not pragmatic context

  6. The man [who I spoke to] • The man [who I spoke to] • He asked [who I spoke to] • * He asked [who I spoke to] • A similar approach can account for the following observations: • It is assumed that the same process is involved in relative clause and interrogative clause formation • But if so, why can the wh-relative delete but not the wh-interrogative? • The wh-relative has an antecedent in the noun that it modifies, so is recoverable. The wh-interrogative does not and so is unrecoverable.

  7. Equi NP Deletion • John wants [Bill to leave] • Bill wants [to leave] • Bill1 wants [Bill1 to leave] • Equi-NP deletion: In structures: ... NP1 ... NP1 ... Delete the second NP

  8. But due to constraints on transformations, deletion transformations fell out of favour • Chomsky and Lasnik (1977) proposed that instead of a deletion, ‘Equi’ structures involve a phonologically null pronoun (PRO): • Bill1 wants [PRO1 to leave] • PRO has two properties that need to be accounted for: • Its referential behaviour (control) • Its distribution

  9. Control • Like most pronouns, PRO can take its reference from an antecedent: • John1 dressed himself1 • John1 thinks Mary likes him1 • John1 wants [PRO1 to be loved]

  10. However, it has special referential properties of its own • Subject/Object control • John1 promised Bill [PRO1 to be good] • John persuaded Bill1 [PRO1 to be good] • Obligatory/Arbitrary control • John1 tried [PRO1/*2 to sing] • [PROarb to sing now] would be inappropriate

  11. The distribution of PRO: the PRO theorem • PRO is an NP • But its distribution is not the same as a typical NP: • I saw him • I spoke to him • He left • * I tried [him to sing] • * I saw PRO • * I spoke to PRO • * PRO left • I tried [PRO to sing]

  12. At first sight it seems that PRO cannot appear in a Case position (it is an exception to the Case Filter) • But there are non-Case positions where PRO cannot go either • * John’s picture PRO • * John is very fond PRO • So the restriction on the distribution of PRO is more stringent

  13. Government • Government is a relationship between certain elements (governors) and certain positions: • Governors = lexical heads (N, V, P and A) and finite Inflection • Governors govern complement and specifier positions: • XPspec X’ X comp

  14. Case assigners are governors • (but not all governors are Case assignors) • So the set of all Case positions is a subset of the set of all governed positions: Governed positions Case positions

  15. PRO must be ungoverned • Therefore it cannot appear in a Case position Governed positions Case positions PRO

  16. Explaining the PRO theorem • Anaphors (reflexive pronouns and NP traces) must have a close by antecedent • John1 admires himself1 • * John1 thinks [Mary admires himself1] • John1 was admired t1 • * John1 was believed [Mary to admire t1]

  17. Pronominals (personal pronouns) cannot have a close by antecedent: • * John1 admires him1 • John1 thinks [Mary admires him1] • Pronominals don’t have to have antecedents at all (anaphors do): • He left • * himself left

  18. There is a part of the structure which contains (at least) the pronoun and a governor = the governing category • Binding theory • A: an anaphor must be bound in its governing category • B: a pronominal must be free in its governing category • Bound = coindexed with an appropriate antecedent • Free = not bound • So pronominals and anaphors are in complementary distribution

  19. (Controled) PRO is like an anaphor • Because it must have an antecedent • (Arbitrary) PRO is like a pronominal • Because it does not need an antecedent • So PRO is a pronominal anaphor • So PRO must be bound and free in its governing category • But this is a contradiction!!! • The contradiction can be solved if PRO has no governing category • PRO will have no governing category if it is not governed • Hence the PRO theorem

  20. A typology of empty categories: * doesn’t exist because all (overt) NPs must have Case and therefore must be governed ** exists, but not in English: missing subject of finite clause in e.g. (most) Romance languages, Slavic languages, Semitic languages, Hungarian, etc.

More Related