1 / 20

Better Ways to Cut a Cake

Better Ways to Cut a Cake. Steven Brams – NYU Mike Jones – Montclair State University Christian Klamler – Graz University Paris, October 2006. Fair Division 2. Various Procedures (Brams & Taylor 1996) Comparisons on the basis of: Complexity of the rules Properties satisfied

afra
Download Presentation

Better Ways to Cut a Cake

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Better Ways to Cut a Cake Steven Brams – NYU Mike Jones – Montclair State University Christian Klamler – Graz University Paris, October 2006

  2. Fair Division 2 • Various Procedures (Brams & Taylor 1996) • Comparisons on the basis of: • Complexity of the rules • Properties satisfied • Manipulability • Division of a heterogeneous divisible good among various players • land division, • service used over time by different players

  3. Desirable Properties3 • Efficiency • There is no other allocation that is better for one player and at least as good for all others. • Envy-freeness • Each player thinks it receives at least a tied-for-largest portion, so it does not envy another player. • Equitability • Each player’s valuation of the portion that it receives is the same as every other player’s valuation of the portion it receives.

  4. 0 1 Assumptions 4 • CAKE as the unit interval X=[0,1] • Cuts divide the cake into subintervals • Every player i has a continuous value function vion[0,1] with the following properties: • For all x  X, vi(x)  0 • vi() = 0 i.e. measure is non-atomic • For any disjoint x,y  X, vi(x+y) = vi(x) + vi(y), i.e. measure is finitely additive • vi(X) = 1 • Players are ignorant about other players’ value functions. • Goal of each player is to maximize the value of the minimum-size piece that it can guarantee for itself, regardless of what the other players do (maximin value), i.e. players are risk-averse; they never choose strategies that entail the possibility of giving them less than their maximin values.

  5. 0 1/2 1 Cut and Choose5 Satisfies Efficiency, Envy-Freeness but NOT Equitability

  6. 2/3 1/2 0 1 1/2 Does a “perfect” cut exist?6 Efficient, envy-free and equitable solution at x = 3/7 (see Jones (2002)) However, (even risk averse) players have no incentive to state their true value functions!

  7. The Surplus Procedure7 RULES: • Independently, A and B report their value functions fA(x) and fB(x) to a referee. • Referee determines the 50-50 points a and b. 0---------------------a-------------b---------1 • If a and b coincide, the cake is cut at that point and the pieces are randomly assigned. • Let a be to the left of b. Then A gets [0,a] and B gets [b,1].

  8. The Surplus Procedure8 • Let c be the point in [a,b] at which the players receive the same proportion p of the cake in this interval as each values it. 0---------------------a-----c--------b---------1 A receives portion [a,c] and B [c,b] for a total of [0,c] for A and (c,1] for B.

  9. The Surplus Procedure9 To solve for c we set: For the previous example we get: Which yields c = 7/16. This does not ensure “pure” equitability as they value the interval [a,b] differently – only proportional equitability!

  10. The Surplus Procedure10 For “pure” equitability we need to cut the cake at point e such that: for e = 3/7 (which is further to the left than c). There are conflicting arguments for cutting at c (proportional equitability) and e (equitability). Property: A procedure is strategy-vulnerable if a maximin player can, by misrepresenting its value function, assuredly do better, whatever the value function of the other players. A procedure that is not strategy-vulnerable is called strategy-proof.

  11. Theorem 111 Theorem 1: SP is strategy-proof, whereas any procedure that makes e the cut-point is strategy-vulnerable. Proof: • Misrepresenting a and/or b. 0-----------a-----b---a’------------1 • Misrepresenting their value functions over [a,b]. 0-----------a-----c----b----------1 Shift of c to the right for A possible if it either • decreases • increases But therefore A would have to know fB(x) which it does not!

  12. Theorem 112 If A knew the location of b manipulation was possible: • concentrate the value just to the left of b, what moves c rightward • Manipulation is possible when cake is cut at e! • submit fA(x) with the same 50-50 point • if a is to the left of b, then decrease • if a is to the right of b, then decrease

  13. Extensions to Three or More Players13 Consider the following value functions for 3 players:

  14. Extensions to Three or More Players14 It is not always possible to divide a cake among three players into envy-free and equitable portions using two cuts!

  15. Extensions to Three or More Players15 However, an envy-freeallocation that uses n-1 parallel, vertical cuts is always efficient. (Gale, 1993; Brams and Taylor, 1996) • There are 2 envy-free procedures for 3-person, 2-cut cake division: • Stromquist (1980): requires 4 simultaneously moving knifes • Barbanel & Brams (2004): requires 2 simultaneously moving knifes Beyond 4 players, no procedure is known that yields an envy-free division unless an unbounded number of cuts is allowed.

  16. Equitability Procedure (EP) 16 It isalways possible to find an equitable division of a cake among three or more players that is efficient. The rules of EP are: • Independently, A,B,C, … report their (possibly false) value functions fA(x), fB(x), fC(x), … over [0,1] to a referee. • The referee determines the cutpoints that equalize the common value that all players receive (for the n! possible assignments of pieces) • Choose the assignment that gives the players their maximum common value.

  17. Equitability Procedure (EP) 17 Using the above 3-player example, the cutpoints e1 and e2 have to be such that: giving e1≈ 0.269 and e2 ≈ 0.662 with a value of 0.393 for each player.

  18. Theorems 2 and 3 18 Theorem 2: EP is strategy-proof. In order to misrepresent, a player would have to know the borders of the pieces. As it does not do so it cannot ensure itself a more valuable piece. Theorem 3: If a player is truthful under EP, it will receive at least 1/n of the cake regardless of whether or not the other players are truthful; otherwise, it may not. We know that there is a division where each player receives at least 1/n (e.g. Dubins-Spanier moving knife procedure). As vi(X)=1, undervaluing the cake at one part will overvalue it at some other part, but an ignorant player might get the latter.

  19. Example 19 In the previous example assume C knows the value functions of A and B. Let c1 and c2 be the cutpoints. Then C should undervalue the middle portion between those points so that: It is maximal if B is indifferent between receiving the right portion and the middle portion, i.e. This leads to c1 ≈ 0.230 and c2 ≈ 0.707 where A and B receive a value of 0.354 and C receives a value of 0.477 (compared to the 0.393 before). However, a bit more undervaluation  C gets a value less than 0.393.

  20. Conclusion 20 • We have described a new 2-person, 1-cut cake cutting procedure (SP). • Like cut-and-choose it induces players to be truthful, but produces a proportionally equitable division. • SP is more information demanding. • For three persons, there may be no envy-free division that is also equitable. For four persons, there is no known minimal-cut envy-free procedure. However, EP ensures equitability and efficiency.

More Related