1 / 30

How Should Presidents Be Elected?

How Should Presidents Be Elected?. E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study. Voting rule method for choosing candidate on basis of ballot (set of available candidates) voters’ preferences (rankings) over candidates prominent examples

Download Presentation

How Should Presidents Be Elected?

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. How Should Presidents Be Elected? E. Maskin Institute for Advanced Study

  2. Voting rule method for choosing candidate on basis of ballot (set of available candidates) voters’ preferences (rankings) over candidates prominent examples plurality rule (MPs in Britain, members of Congress in U.S.) choose candidate ranked first by more voters than any other majority rule (Condorcet Method) choose candidate preferred by majority to each other candidate 2

  3. run-off voting (presidential elections in France) • choose candidate ranked first by more voters than any other, unless gets less than majority among top 2 candidates, choose one preferred by majority • rank-order voting (Borda Count) • candidate assigned 1 point every time voter ranks her first, 2 points every time ranked second, etc. • choose candidate with lowest vote total • utilitarianism • choose candidate that maximizes sum of voters’ utilities

  4. Which voting rule to adopt? • Voting theorist’s answer: • specify what one wants (axioms) • see which rules satisfy the axioms • But basic negative results: Arrow Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem • if 3 or more candidates, no voting rule satisfies set of compelling axioms

  5. Prompts question: Which voting rule(s) satisfy axioms most often? try to answer question today based on series of papers with P. Dasgupta 5

  6. X = finite set of conceivable candidates • society = continuum of voters [0,1] • reason for continuum clear soon • utility function for voter i • restrict attention to strict utility functions • profile

  7. voting rule F • winning candidates (could be ties) • Example – plurality rule

  8. Axioms that is, there is clear-cut winner but that is too much to ask for e.g., with plurality rule exact ties are possible might be 2 candidates who are both ranked first the most still, with large number of voters, tie very unlikely similarly with majority rule, rank-order voting, etc. continuum helps formalize this 8

  9. fraction of electorate who prefer x to y profile is regular if proportions of voters preferring one candidate to another fall outside exceptional set: Generic Decisiveness (GD): There exists finite S such that 9

  10. if everybody prefers x to y, then y should not win when x is on the ballot winner should not depend on which voter has which preferences names don’t matter all voters treated symmetrically all candidates treated symmetrically 10

  11. only preference rankings matter strength of preference not captured rules out utilitarianism reflects standard idea that preference strength has no operational meaning if only one “good” (no choice experiment) implied by later axiom could be replaced by cardinality (as in von Neumann-Morgenstern preferences) what’s important: no interpersonal comparisons such comparisons not operational 11

  12. next axiom most controversial but has compelling rationale invoked by Arrow (1951) and Nash (1950) then if x elected and then some non-elected candidate removed from ballot, x still elected no “spoilers” (e.g. Nader in 2000 U.S. presidential election, Le Pen in 2002 French presidential election) Nash formulation 12

  13. plurality rule violates I so do rank-order voting and run-off voting majority rule satisfies I but violates GD 13

  14. Theorem 1: No voting rule satisfies GD, P, A, N, O, and I analog of Arrow Impossibility Theorem But natural follow-up question: Which voting rule (s) satisfies axioms as often as possible? have to clarify “as often as possible” 14

  15. F 15

  16. i.e., 16

  17. Let S be exceptional for F. Because S finite, there exists n such that if divide population into n equal groups assign everybody in a group same utility function resulting profile regular w.r.t. S. 17

  18. Consider Consider then 18

  19. Continuing iteratively 19

  20. Conversely, suppose F does not 20

  21. Consider 21

  22. Final Axiom: • Nonmanipulability (NM): then • the members of coalition C can’t all gain from misrepresenting

  23. Lemma: If F satisfies NM and I, F satisfies O • NM rules out utilitarianism

  24. But majority rule also violates NM • one possibility

  25. Theorem 3: There exists no voting rule satisfying GD, P,A,N,I and NM Proof: similar to that of Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem

  26. Conversely, suppose Proof: From NM and I, if F works very well on U , F must be ordinal • Hence result follows from • Theorem 2

  27. Let’s drop I • most controversial • GS again • Fworks nicely on U if satisfies GD,P,A,N,NM on U

  28. Theorem 5: • Suppose F works nicely on U , Proof:

  29. Striking that the 2 longest-studied voting rules (Condorcet and Borda) are also • only two that work nicely on maximal domains

More Related