1 / 23

Quantum Measurements: some technical background

“Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments, et cetera von Neumann measurements (entanglement and decoherence) Slides, and some other useful links, to be posted: http://www.physics.utoronto.ca/~steinberg/QMP.html.

siusan
Download Presentation

Quantum Measurements: some technical background

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments, et cetera von Neumann measurements (entanglement and decoherence) Slides, and some other useful links, to be posted: http://www.physics.utoronto.ca/~steinberg/QMP.html Quantum Measurements:some technical background (AKA: the boring lecture) 14 Oct 2003

  2. The measurement postulate

  3. ...measurement outcomes... “Collapse of the wavefunction” Future measurements of A will of course agree with this ai Measurement State preparation

  4. + = Obviously, if I open my left hand and measure the colour of its pawn, I find either black or white, not both – from that point on, I describe the left pawn as one colour eigenstate, or . What are the effects of measurement? Suppose we have two pawns, one black and one white, and I put one in each hand – we can write this state as something like Is the other pawn still in a state of uncertain colour? No – obviously, its state has also been “affected” by this measurement.

  5. When ai is found, the state More refined version:the “projection postulate” Of course, this is not normalized, so the final state is actually Finding the left pawn to be black leaves the system in a state where the right pawn is known to be white (unsurprisingly).

  6. det. 1 det. 2 Two effects of measurement One thing happens, as opposed to all other possibilities Interference between the different possibilities becomes impossible. 100% 50% 50% What’s the state of the particles before the final beam-splitter? If no bomb was present, half the particles are in path A and half are in path B. If the bomb “measures” which path each is in... then still, half are in path A and half are in path B. The measurement didn’t change the probabilistic description of the state... but without the bomb, interference caused all particles to interfere at the final beam splitter and go left; with the bomb, there is no such interference. Measurement destroyed phase information, but left the probabilities unchanged. |A + ei|B  |A “OR” |B . A B

  7. How does the bomb cause the other detector to fire? The probability is given by the absolute square of this inner product, which is 1/4 + 1/4 = 1/2 (because the orthogonality of "peace" and "BOOM" cause the cross-terms to vanish).

  8. Sneaky fact... No one knows why one thing happens instead of many simultaneous things... in fact, no one knows whether this is true (cf. “relative-state”, “many-worlds”, “many-minds” interpretations). No “collapse” process has ever been observed – i.e., no case where we would make the wrong predictions if we didn’t assume collapse. Yet to make sense of probabilities, one typically assumes that by the time you measure something, it’s one thing or another. (But how do you know that when I measured it, I wasn’t still in a probabilistic state? “Wigner’s friend.”) We can try (a) to understand what measurements do to coherence and/or (b) to search for a real “collapse” process, supplementary to quantum mechanics as we know it.

  9. "Pure states" individual QM wave functions "Mixed states" probabilistic mixtures of QM states. (e.g., results of measurements) "Density Matrices" We need a formalism for this... Note that in that interferometer, |A  |det. 1 and |det. 2; |B  |det. 1 and |det. 2; but |A + |B  |det. 2 only (because of interference). The state "|A OR |B" might be |A (and get to det. 1 half the time)... or it might be |B (and get to det. 1 half the time). It's not|A + |B, |A – |B, etc. Any QM wave function you write down which is half A and half B will exhibit some interference; no wave function can describe the state after such a measurement. Technical example: there is no spin-1/2 state with <SZ> = <SX> = 0.

  10. Intro to density matrices...

  11. Diagonal elements = probabilities Off-diagonal elements = "coherences" (provide info. about relative phase) Interpretation of matrix elements

  12. Connection to observables

  13. The essential property of a statistical mixture is that all expectation values are just the weighted averages of those for the individual pure states. Our expression for expectation values is linear in the density matrix – i.e., we can keep using that expression with mixed states, if we define the mixed-state density matrix itself as a weighted average. And what about mixed states?

  14. Density matrices for mixed states Note: probabilities still 50/50, but no coherence.

  15. What happens if you don't look at part of your system? When you calculate expectation values, you trace over the system. If your operators depend only on a subsystem, then it makes no difference whether you trace over other systems before or after:

  16. Decoherence arises from throwing away information Taking this trace over the environment retains only terms diagonal in the environment variables – i.e., no cross-terms (coherences) remain if they refer to different states of the environment. (If there is any way – even in principle – to tell which of two paths was followed, then no interference may occur.)     s when env is  s when env is 

  17. ... coherence lost There is still coherence between  and , but if the environment is not part of your interferometer, you may as well consider it to have "collapsed" to  or  . This means there is no effective coherence if you look only at the system.

  18. Decoherence: the party line When a particle interacts with a measurement device, the two subsystems become entangled (no separable description). Coherence is still present, but only in the entire system; if there is enough information in the measurement device to tell which path your subsystem followed, then it is impossible to observe interference without looking at both parts of the system. The effective density matrix of your system (traced over states of the measuring apparatus) is that of a mixed state. Coherence is never truly lost, as unitary evolution preserves the purity of states. In principle, this measurement interaction is reversible. In practice, once the system interacts with the "environment", i.e., anything with too many degrees of freedom for us to handle, we cannot reverse it. Just as in classical statistical mechanics, it is the approximation of an open system which leads to effective irreversibility, and loss of information (increase of entropy). Loss of Information = Loss of Coherence

  19. So, how does a system become "entangled" with a measuring device? • First, recall: Bohr – we must treat measurement classically • Wigner – why must we? • von Neumann:there are two processes in QM: Unitary and Reduction. He shows how all the effects of measurement we've described so far may be explained without any reduction, or macroscopic devices. • [Of course, this gets us a diagonal density matrix – classical probabilities without coherence – but still can't tell us how those probabilities turn into one occurrence or another.] To measure some observable A, let a "meter" interact with it, so the bigger A is, the more the pointer on the meter moves. P is the generator of translations, so this just means we allow the system and meter to interact according to Hint A P.

  20. The pointer position evolves at a rate proportional to <A>. An aside (more intuitive?) Suppose instead of looking at the position of our pointer, we used its velocity to take a reading. In other words, let the particle exert a force on the pointer, and have the force be proportional to A; then the pointer's final velocity will be proportional to A too. F = g A U(x) = g A X Hint = g A X This works with any pair of conjugate variables. In the standard case, Hint = g A Px , we can see

  21. Initial State of System Final state of both (entangled) Hint=gApx System-pointer coupling Initial State of Pointer x x A A A von Neumann measurement

  22. Back-Action In other words, the measurement does not simply cause the pointer position to evolve, while leaving the system alone. The interaction entangles the two, and as we have seen, this entanglement is the source of decoherence. It is often also described as "back-action" of the measuring device on the measured system. Unless Px, the momentum of the pointer, is perfectly well-defined, then the interaction Hamiltonian Hint = g A Px looks like an uncertain (noisy) potential for the particle. A high-resolution measurement needs a well-defined pointer position X. This implies (by Heisenberg) that Px is not well-defined. The more accurate the measurement, the greater the back-action. Measuring A perturbs the variable conjugate to A "randomly" (unless, that is, you pay attention to entanglement).

  23. Summary We have no idea whether or not "collapse" really occurs. Any time two systems interact and we discard information about one of them, this can be thought of as a measurement, whether or not either is macroscopic, & whether or not there is collapse. The von Neumann interaction shows how the two systems become entangled, and how this may look like random noise from the point of view of the subsystem. The "reduced density matrix" of an entangled subsystem appears mixed, because the discarded parts of the system carry away information. This is the origin of decoherence of the measured subsystem.

More Related