1 / 36

Property Rights and Collective Action in Natural Resources with Application to Mexico

Property Rights and Collective Action in Natural Resources with Application to Mexico. Lecture 1: Introduction to the political economy of natural resources Lecture 2: Theories of collective action, cooperation, and common property

Download Presentation

Property Rights and Collective Action in Natural Resources with Application to Mexico

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Property Rights and Collective Action in Natural Resources with Application to Mexico Lecture 1: Introduction to the political economy of natural resources Lecture 2: Theories of collective action, cooperation, and common property Lecture 3: Principal-agent analysis and institutional organization Lecture 4: Incomplete contracts with application to Mexico Lecture 5: A political economy model Lecture 6: Power and the distribution of benefits with application to Mexico Lecture 7: Problems with empirical measurement with application to Mexico Lecture 8: Beyond economics: An interdisciplinary perspective

  2. Common Property Resources • Not excludable • – If access is open, anyone can use them. • Rival goods • – One person’s use reduces other’s use.

  3. The Tragedy of the Commons • Garrett Hardin, “The Tragedy of the Commons” (Science, 1968) • Example of common pastureland, open to all. The rational herdsman seeking • to maximize gain will calculate the utility to him of adding one additional animal, • not taking into account the effect of his use on other herdmen. • Thus, each is compelled to add as many animals as possible, leading to overgrazing. • – “Freedom in a commons brings ruin to all.” • Other examples of commons: • –Fisheries • –Free parking meters • – Admission to national parks • Thus, laissez-faire, “Invisible Hand” approaches to • resource allocation need not always provide • the expected optimal solution.

  4. Community Common Property Resources • The word community is used in many ways: • Ecological communities in an ecosystem • Community with defined membership and constitution • Sense of community • Communities of interest • Communities of space • Community forestry • In this workshop we will use (2): community as a group of • people distinguished by a collective property right.  • However, configurations of access and control of property are central: • Who owns it? • Who claims it? • Who makes decisions about it, and how? • Who benefits and incurs cost from it?

  5. Owens Valley: Evolved Community of Interests • In 1900, Los Angeles was doubling in population every five • years, and was running out of water, so Mulholland bought • water rights from rural ranchers in Owens Valley to the North. • The aqueduct to Los Angeles opened in 1913; by 1926 Owens Lake • had disappeared. Mono Lake water levels fell. • Massive dust storms result as the valley dries up. • Lawsuits brought by rural towns and local environmentalists in the • 1980s force Los Angeles to divert some water to the lakes, • to raise water levels and reduce toxic dust. • Current status: community of interests control • Owens Valley lakes. • A story of devolution. The solution • was not governmental, but a local • community acting to preserve • common property resources. Owens Lake today

  6. Imperial Valley: Nonevolved Community of Interests • Water from the Colorado River irrigates the Imperial Valley • and the inland Salton Sea. In 2003, the amount of water • was cut by 11%, while Valley farmers negotiated with • San Diego to sell water to the city for $50 million annually. • Salinity in the Salton Sea increases, killing wildlife and • threatening to make a “dead” lake. • Estimates of the environmental cost of • repairing the lake reach $1 billion. • No devolution, no community of interest Salton Sea

  7. Groundwater in Los Angeles:Initially commons, evolves to self governance (bottom-up) • Legally, the right to pump from groundwater basins was established by a history • of continuous withdrawal and beneficial use. • “Rule of capture” governs ownership of the stock, when property rights are • undefined and access nonexclusive. • –Pumpers are granted exclusive rights to what they pump; what they do not • pump will be taken (in part) by rivals. • –The result was pumping far beyond sustainable levels, with saltwater incursion • and threatened collapse of groundwater basins. • Solution: In 1943, negotiations began to reduce pumping from Raymond Basin • –With the threat of lawsuits looming, stakeholders negotiated an agreement to • share the cutback to safe levels proportionately, rather than determine in • court whose rights took precedence. • –By negotiating their own agreement, the parties ended the pumping race faster • and at a lower cost, while gaining firm and marketable rights to defined • shares of the safe yield of the basin. • –Later litigation in nearby basins resulted in management costs 25 times higher.

  8. Irrigation in Sri Lanka:Initially commons, evolves to self governance (top-down) • Maldistribution due to lack of collective action. • Gal Oya irrigation system is the largest in Sri Lanka, completed in 1950 • The acreage actually irrigated turned out to be only one-third of projections • – Engineers presumed that water would be treated as a scare good with strict • allocation rules; neither presumption was appropriate. • Incentive structure for rice farmers reinforced a short-term “individualistic” strategy • – Take as much water as their paddy fields will hold, legally or illegally, while refraining • from participation in any system that would limit water use. • In 1980s, Agrarian Research and Training Institute organizes farmers into small-scale, • informal, grassroots organizations, to educate and • problem-solve. • Under self-governance, water distribution becomes • more equitable. Canal Belihul Oya, Sri Lanka

  9. Fisheries: Commons • In Sri Lanka, open access to ocean fisheries combined with • improved boats and nets has led to a precipitous decline • in stock. • Fisherman have to go farther out to catch fish, increasing • their risk of death. • The limit of entry is the risk of death. • Attempts to set rules have been proposed but not • implemented, due to ongoing • civil war. Sri Lankan fishing boats

  10. Formal Definitions of Terms • Coalition formation • Participation constraints • Incentive compatibility • Alignment of incentives • Mechanism design • Property rights

  11. Coalition Formation • A subset of stakeholders whose interests are more closely • aligned with each other’s than with other stakeholders. • Nash/Harsanyi model of bargaining and policy formation

  12. Participation Constraints • The point at which a player’s payoff for participation • is equal to their payoff in the disagreement • outcome. • Unless this constraint is satisfied a person in the community • will not become a member of a coalition.

  13. Incentive Compatibility • An allocation mechanism for which participants in the • process would not find it advantageous to violate the • rules of the process. • Any institution or rule designed to accomplish group • goals must be incentive compatible if it is to perform • as desired. • If a mechanism is incentive compatible, then each agent • knows that his best strategy is to follow the rules according • to his true characteristic, no matter what the other agents do.

  14. Alignment of Incentives • Stakeholders share a common interest • If there is a conflict of interest, there cannot be • alignment of incentives

  15. Principal-Agent Problem • Agent: an individual employed by a principal to achieve the • principal’s objective • Principal: an individual who employs one or more agents to • achieve an objective • Problem arises when agents (e.g., a firm’s managers) pursue • their own goals rather than the goals of the principals (e.g., • the firm’s owners).

  16. Mechanism Design • Explicitly recognizes the possibility of institutional failure • Asymmetric information: • –Moral hazard/Hidden action • –Hidden information • Adverse selection • Signaling • Strategic Behavior and False Signals

  17. The Analytical Dimensions of Community Policy • Analytical frameworks for the study of community • policy typically focus on one of four dimensions: • Incidence • Implementation • Political Economy • Governance Structures

  18. Incidence • Uses partial equilibrium frameworks, based on a number of • simplifying assumptions: • Markets are perfect in the absence of government • intervention; any introduction of policy is by • construction a government failure. • Assumes: • –Perfect implementation (PI) • –No feedback effects from interest groups (NF) • –A given governance structure (GG)

  19. Implementation • Explicitly recognizes the possibility of institutional failure • Does not presume perfect implementation (PI) • Policy analyses that recognizes agents actively respond • to incentives. • Asymmetric information: • –Moral hazard/Hidden action • –Hidden information • Adverse selection • Signaling • Incentive compatibility • Participation constraints

  20. Political Economy • The assumption of no feedback effects from interest • group formation (NF) is relaxed. • Seeks to explain the selection and implementation of actual • public policies by endogenizing the instrument choice as a • function of the actions of stakeholders. • Political economic theories include: University of Chicago, • rent-seeking, public choice, liberal-pluralist, “theory of the • state”, political-economic bargaining • Empirical formulations: structural, constraints, policy reaction • functions, reduced form representations • Political preference function (PPF)

  21. Governance • A constitutional analytical dimension, that relaxes the given • governance structure assumption (GG) • A constitutional design establishes the rules by which rule are made, • setting the boundaries for economic, political and civil freedoms. • Conceptual frameworks: views current policies as a rational outcome • of the collective decision-making process. • If power is unevenly distributed among the special interests and societal • interests, organizational failures naturally arise. • The resulting distribution of political power and influence creates a • tradeoff between public and special interest in the selection of particular policies. • Formal Determination: • – Bargaining Issues • – Stakeholder Access • – Admissible Coalitions • – Default Options

  22. Constitutional Rules and Policymaking Centers • The major ideas that emerge in constitutional prescription can be illustrated by means of a simple example of three policymaking centers faced with a two-dimensional, group-choice problem in which any one of four possible constitutional rules may be selected. • Even though this is a simplified example, it nevertheless graphically captures the essential features of the constitutional selection problem. • The preferences of the individual policy centers among the various policy combinations are represented by the indifference curves drawn in Figure 9.1.

  23. Preferences and collective choice for three policymaking centers x2 U21 U22 U23 U24 U35 B G U20 U14 U34 U13 F E Location of a Public Good from City U33 I H U12 J U32 U31 U11 D C A U30 U10 0 x1 Investment Timing

  24. Preferences and collective choice for three policymaking centers, continued • Points A, B, and C represent the policy combinations most favored by policy center 1, 2, and 3, respectively; and the utility levels associated with the various indifference curves satisfy the relation, • As travel costs are borne by the consumers of the public goods, policy centers 1 and 3, who happen to represent neighboring consumer interests, prefer essentially the same site location. • Policy center 1 is more impatient than policy center 2 who, in turn, is more impatient than policy center 3. • The policy center’s time preferences are revealed by their attitude toward the timing of the government’s investment in the public good. • The more impatient the policy center, the sooner they prefer the investment and associated financing take place.

  25. Preferences and collective choice for three policymaking centers, continued • The lines, AB, AC, and BC, connecting the most favored combinations are loci where the indifference curves of policy center i and policy center j are tangential to each other; i.e., they are the corresponding contract curves. • Note that for any policy combination outside , there is at least one combination in which is Pareto superior to it and will, therefore, be unanimously preferred by all policy • centers.

  26. There is a large set of constitutional rules that could be evaluated—expert rule (or almost expert rule), tie-breaking chairman rule, rule of the chairman and two aids, unanimity, restricted simple majority rule, multiple majority rule, simple majority rule. • Assume that only four collective choice rules are admissible at the constitutional phase. These rules are: Rules • : Elect one policy center who will serve as the sole decision maker on all policy issues (“president”). • : Conduct a referendum over pairs of policy alternatives where the winner in each pair is decided by simple majority, and no bargaining and/or coalition formation is permitted (“referendum”). • : Use the same procedure as under referendum, but bargaining and coalition formation are allowed (“voting cum bargaining”). • : Select a policy combination with which all policy centers concur (“unanimity”).

  27. Evaluation of Alternative Constitutional Rules: Presidential System • Under a presidential system ( ), there are three possible political solutions: A, B, and C. • The policy center’s expected utility is then

  28. Evaluation of Alternative Constitutional Rules: Referendum • If a referendum ( ) is selected, every point in is a likely candidate for a solution since the path selected in the operation phase cannot be foretold with certainty. • The policy center’s expected utility is then where is the area of .

  29. Evaluation of Alternative Constitutional Rules: Voting cum bargaining • Under voting cum bargaining ( ), the set of possible political solutions depends on the solution concept employed. • There are three possible solutions: policy combination D corresponding to the coalition structure ; policy combination E corresponding to coalition structure ; policy combination F corresponding to coalition structure • . Under this constitutional rule, the policy center’s expected utility is

  30. Evaluation of Alternative Constitutional Rules: Unanimity • The political solution under unanimity ( ) is the outcome of a bargaining game and depends again on the solution concept employed. • The policy center’s expected utility is then

  31. Let denote the cost of reaching a decision (“decision cost”) per policy center associated with the selection of constitutional rule; then one expects . • Note that consists mostly of the negotiation cost but may include other types of costs, such as losses due to calculation errors. • is the smallest since, under the presidential system assumed here, collective decisions are made by a single person. • is the greatest, since, under unanimity, each individual enjoys a veto power. • is greater than since involves bargaining • while does not. Bargaining Costs

  32. Bargaining Costs, continued • Even though the mean values of the political solutions under alternative constitutional rules are similar, large differences exist among the corresponding spreads. • When is small, a political solution maximizing the well-being of policy centers in at the expense of those not in is easily attained. • When is large, its policy centers’ preferences are more diverse and the solution agreed upon by policy centers in is less likely to maximize their preferences at the expense of the policy centers excluded from .

  33. Bargaining Costs, continued • The disparity is greatest under the presidential system and smallest under the unanimity rule , with the voting rules • ( and ) occupying an intermediate position. • The difference in the spreads of political outcomes associated with the two voting rules derives from a completely different source—the wide range of possible “decision paths” under referendum as compared to the limited and centrally-oriented set of possible solutions under voting cum bargaining . • The general pattern of variation in the policy center’s utility level under the alternative constitutional rules reflects the spread of the policy combinations under these rules.

  34. Bargaining Costs, continued • Note that spread spread spread spread . • Given the “mean preserving spread” argument implied by the above observation, it follows that for sufficiently risk-averse policy centers .

  35. Constitutional Space Prescription • The scope for prescription at the constitutional phase may be decided by alternative rules selected in accordance with the sensitivity of the policy centers’ expected utility to the ultimate decision and its associated cost. • The sole decision-maker case, , exhibits maximal spread but minimal bargaining costs, and it is usually confined to matters of less importance. • To evaluate, define .

  36. The structure of (C, V) over the constitutional rules and policy issues spaces V M4 M3 M2 M4 M3 Expected Utility M1 M2 M1 M4 M3 M2 M1 0 C Decision Costs

More Related