1 / 77

SIGNALING GAMES AND ACCOUNTABILITY

SIGNALING GAMES AND ACCOUNTABILITY. Mario Gilli Department of Economics University of Milano-Bicocca. Introduction In the past twenty years game theoretic models have become a common paradigm in political economics.

Download Presentation

SIGNALING GAMES AND ACCOUNTABILITY

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. SIGNALING GAMES AND ACCOUNTABILITY Mario Gilli Department of Economics University of Milano-Bicocca

  2. Introduction In the past twenty years game theoretic models have become a common paradigm in political economics. Political phenomena have been explained as a consequence of equilibrium behavior related to individual incentives inherent in a political system. Two are the crucial issues at the core of this literature: To select congruent agent as rulers To find the correct mechanism to incentivize congruent political behavior

  3. Signalling games have proved to be an effective means to model both issues, and their interaction. The aim of this paper is to show the effectiveness of this approach providing a general structure applied to different political issues related to the interaction between politicians' incentivation and selection To show the crucial role played by the assumptions on the players’ beliefs to select different equilibria, i.e. different properties of political regimes. The main focus of the paper will be on the role of beliefs on the equilibrium properties of game theoretic models of accountability in political economics.

  4. The precise models analyzed in this paper vary widely, we select the models that have a common structure: models that can be represented as signaling games beliefs’ updating out of equilibrium is crucial, Signaling games are specific incomplete information games where the informed player moves first and in this way might convey information on its private information

  5. The general structure of Signaling Games • THE SIMPLEST POSSIBLE STRUCTURE • Two players: a Sender (S) and a Receiver (R). • The timing of the game is: • (1) nature draws a type for S, denoted t  T, according to the commonly known probability distribution p(t); • (2) S privately observes the type t and then sends the message m  M to R; and • (3) R observes m and then takes the action a  A. • SIMPLIFICATION: T, M, and A are all finite. • Payoffs are US(t,m,a) and UR(t,m,a). • Everything but t, is common knowledge.

  6. A possible game tree Sender receiver Nature receiver Sender

  7. Sequential Rationality in Extensive Form Games After the Harsanyi transformation, signaling games are just a specific class of extensive form games with imperfect information. A well known problem of equilibrium behavior in extensive form games is that choices out of the equilibrium path are unrestricted by expected utility maximization, since they are conditioned to zero probability event. The fact is that in a Nash Equilibrium each player must act optimally given the other players' strategies However, this means that optimality condition is imposed at the beginning of the game only. Entry game as example.

  8. The Entry Game The first equilibrium: Enter, Accomodate 0, 0 Smash Enter 2 Accommodate 1 2, 2 Stay Out 1, 5

  9. Thesecond equilibrium: Stay Out-Smash 0, 0 Smash Enter 2 Accommodate 1 2, 2 Stay Out 1, 5

  10. Meaning of the second equilibrium: Stay Out, Smash • Threat by 2: ifyouwillenter, I will smash you • Butonce 2 iscalled to play, will 2 have the incentive to carry out the threat? • If YES, the action is credible • If NO, the action is noncredible • In thisequilibrium, if2will be asked to play, then 2 willprefer to accomodate: the threatis non credible • How isitpossible in a Nash equilibrium? • Nash Equilibrium: each player must act optimally given the other players' strategies, i.e., play a best response to the others' strategies. • Problem: Optimality condition only at the beginning of the game

  11. Out of equilibrium information sets • In dynamic games there are equilibrium paths that do not reach some information sets: these are the out-of-equilibrium information sets • The optimality conditions of Nash equilibria does not constrain behavior at these nodes, but • these information sets are out-of-equilibriumbecause of the actions the players are supposed to play at these nodes • In other words, reaching these nodes in equilibrium is a zero probability event, but this probability is endogeneous, because is derived from the players’ equilibrium behavior.

  12. Out of equilibrium information sets in the entry game • Formally: • Suppose 1 plays Stay out • Then player 2’s payoff does not depend on his strategy • Therefore any 2’s strategy is a best reply to 1’s SO

  13. Sequential Rationality • An optimal strategy for a player should maximize his or her payoff, conditional on every information set at which this player has the move • In other words, player i’s strategy should specify an “optimal” action at each of player i’s information sets, even those that have zero endogenous probability to be reached THUS • Apply some notion of rational behavior any time you face a well defined decision situation. • This implies that players takes action that they do have an incentive (according to that notion of rational behavior) to carry out, once the information set is reached, even if it had ex ante zero probability.

  14. The Entry Game The first equilibrium is the only one satisfying sequential rationality 0, 0 Smash Enter 2 Accommodate 1 2, 2 Stay Out 1, 5

  15. SequentialRationality: a problem • An optimal strategy for a player should maximize his or her payoff, conditional on every information set at which this player has the move • However in some information sets, the optimal action depends • On the other players’ future behavior • On the decision nodes of the information set • the optimal choice of 1 depends on 2 actions in {x, x’} • In {x, x’} 2 would choose l if x, r if x’ R 1 0 2 R 1 M L x’ 2 x l r l r -3 -1 1 -2 3 1 -2 -1 15

  16. Construction of a formal definition of sequential rationality: notation • A behavior strategy for player i is the collection where for each hHi and each aA(h), hi(a)  0 and • hi(a) is a probability distribution that describes i's behavior at information set h. •  = (1,...,n) •  -i = (1,...,i-1,i+1,...,n).

  17. Construction of a formal definition of sequential rationality: definitions • A system of beliefs is a specification  h(x) for each information set h, where •  h(x)  0 is the probability player i assesses that a node x  h  Hi has been reached, GIVEN h  Hi . • Therefore • Anassessment is a beliefs-strategies pair (,).

  18. Definition of SEQUENTIAL RATIONALITYfor imperfect information games An assessment (,) is sequentially rational if given the beliefs  • no player i prefers at any information set h  Hi to change her strategy hi • In other words, • each player’s behavior strategy is a best response at any information set h  Hi, given her beliefs and  -i

  19. Effect of sequential rationality for imperfect information games • First, it eliminates strictly dominated actions from consideration off the equilibrium path: actions are credible • Second, it elevates beliefs to the importance of strategies. • This provides a language — the language of beliefs — for discussing the merits of competing sequentially rational equilibria.

  20. Definition of WEAK PERFECT BAYESIAN EQUILIBRIUM A Weak Perfect Bayesian equilibriumis an assessment (,) such that • each player’s behavior strategy is a best response at any information set h  Hi, given her beliefs and given opponents’ equilibrium behavior, i.e. for any hH, (h) BR(h,  -i) • The beliefs are derived from the equilibrium strategies through Bayes’ rule whenever possible, i.e.

  21. THE PROBLEMS WITH WPBE AND THE NOTION OF SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA

  22. Game 2: WPBE and beliefs R 1 0 2 R 1 M L x’ 2 x l r l r -3 -1 1 -2 3 1 -2 -1 Problem: A WPBE might be supported by strange beliefs Two WPBE: • (RM,r), with 2. (RM,l)with 22

  23. Game 2: deriving beliefs for a WPBE(R-M, l) R 1 0 2 R 1 M L x’ 2 x l r l r -3 -1 1 -2 3 1 -2 -1

  24. Refining the notion of Weak Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium • To solve the previousproblemwetry to refine the notion of WPBE, usingtotallymixedstrategies and definingSEQUENTIALEQUILIBRIA. • A strategy profile  is totally mixed if it assigns strictly positive probability to each action a  A(h) for each information set h  H.

  25. Definition ofSEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIUM • An assessment (,) is consistent if there exists a sequence of totally mixed strategies n and corresponding beliefs n derived from Bayes' rule such that • A sequential equilibrium is an assessment (,) that is both • sequentially rational and • consistent.

  26. Game 2: deriving beliefs with consistency R 1 0 2 R 1 M L x’ 2 x l r l r -3 -1 1 -2 3 1 -2 -1

  27. DIFFERENT REFINEMENTS AND DIFFERENT EXPLANATIONS OF DEVIATIONS

  28. Meaning of SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA • In a SE any equilibrium strategy is approximated by a totally mixed strategy • Because of this, any information set is reached with strictly positive probability possibly vanishing • This means that out of equilibrium information sets are reached with small vanishing probabilities, i.e. by mistakes: impossible events are explained as due to trembling hands.

  29. SIMPLE MISTAKES The simplest explanations of a deviation from the equilibrium path is just a simple mistake: One holds to the hypothesis that all players intend to follow the prescription of the equilibrium, but that they sometimes fail In Signaling Games useful restrictions on out-of-equilibrium beliefs are possible only insofar as one is willing to attribute relative likelihood to particular mistakes.

  30. Sequential Equilibria in Signaling Games Therefore any out-of-equilibrium beliefsis possible both with WPBE and with SE. The value of μ will depend on p¹ versus p², i.e. whether we believe is more likely that t¹ or t² has deviated from SE

  31. MISTAKEN THEORIES (1) Deviations from equilibrium play may be explained by the fact that one or more players does not understand what is expected of him or wish to signal something One would then look for relatively likely alternative theories for how to play the game to explain Who has defected What has been the nature of defection Why some player has deviated , e.g. what might be the consequences of that defection for later play. Structural consistency is a way of formalizing this type of reasoning.

  32. MISTAKEN THEORIES (2) this reasoning can lead to direct attack to Sequential Equilibrium, in particular to the hypothesis that player countenance no further deviations from the equilibrium when evaluating what to do in the face of an apparent deviation, for example if after a deviation one believes that the error in theory may be one’s own, then deviations among different players may be thought to be correlated. Forward Induction: a deviation might be due to a prospective attempt to get a better payoff, e.g. a deviation from a specified equilibrium is said to be "bad" if it always yields the deviator less than her equilibrium payoff in every circumstance, according to FI this deviation should generate beliefs equal to zero

  33. Example of an implausible WPBE R 1 1 1 M L x’ 2 x l r l r 2 -1 -4 -2 0 -1 -1 -2 (A,r) seems unreasonable because it requires player 2 to believe with high probability that player 1 has made a bad deviation from the equilibrium: it is not a forward induction equilibriumLimitations: in more complex games the set of bad deviations often is empty

  34. SIGNALING GAMESEQUILIBRIA & BELIEFS

  35. Types of equilibria • POOLING EQUILIBRIUM: An equilibrium where all types of informed players do the same thing, thus no information is provided by informed actions • SEPARATING EQUILIBRIUM: An equilibrium where all types of informed players do different thing, thus information is perfectly revealed by informed actions • SEMISEPARATING EQUILIBRIUM: An equilibrium where some types of informed players do different thing, thus information is partially revealed by informed actions

  36. Example of possible pooling equilibrium

  37. Example of possible separating equilibrium

  38. Example of possible semiseparating equilibrium

  39. Refinements in Signalling Games

  40. Beer and Quiche: The Entry-Deterrence Problem 1;2 duel 0;2 duel beer quiche x y not not 2;1 3;1 wimp 0.1 N surly 0.9 1;0 duel 0;0 duel y’ x’ beer quiche not not 3;1 2;1

  41. Beer and Quiche: Two Sequential Equilibria • Two SE, both pooling: • (BB; ND): both types drink beer, and the entrant duels if quiche is observed but declines to duel if beer is observed. To find a WPBE we should derive the possible beliefs that makes such decisions sequentially rational • (QQ; DN): both types have quiche, the entrant duels if beer is observed but declines to duel if quiche is observed. To find a WPBE we should derive the possible beliefs that makes such decisions sequentially rational.

  42. First Sequential Equilibrium The first pooling SE (BB; ND) with beliefs: Hence ND shouldsatisfy Then the SE is (BB; ND), (x|{x,x’}) = 0.1, (y|{y,y’}) ≥ 0.5.

  43. First SE: beer-beer, then μ(x|{x.x’})=0.1& μ(y|{y,y’})[0,1];μ(x|{x.x’})=0.1 implies not. In turn this implies that 1will not deviate if and only if 2 duel in {y,y’}, i.e. μ(y|{y.y’}) > 1/2 1;2 duel 0;2 duel beer quiche x y not not 2;1 3;1 wimp 0.1 N surly 0.9 1;0 duel 0;0 duel y’ x’ beer quiche not not 3;1 2;1

  44. First Sequential Equilibria • Both types drink beer, and the entrant duels if quiche is observed but declines to duel if beer is observed. In such an equilibrium, the decision to duel following quiche is rationalized by any off-the-equilibrium-path belief that puts sufficiently high probability (at least 1/2) on the incumbent being wimpy given that the non equilibrium choice “quiche” has been observed: μ(y|{y,y’}) = μ(W|Q)> 1/2

  45. Second Sequential Equilibrium The second pooling SE (QQ; DN): Hence DN shouldsatisfy Then the SE is (QQ; DN), (x|{x,x’}) ≥ 0.5, (y|{y,y’}) = 0.1

  46. Second SE:quiche-quiche, then μ(y|{y,y’})=0.1& μ(x|{x,x’})[0,1];μ(y|{y,y’})=0.1 implies not. In turn this implies that 1will not deviate if and only if 2 duel in {x,x’}, i.e. μ(x|{x,x’})>1/2 1;2 duel 0;2 duel beer quiche x y not not 2;1 3;1 wimp 0.1 N surly 0.9 1;0 duel 0;0 duel y’ x’ beer quiche not not 3;1 2;1

  47. Second Sequential Equilibria • Both types have quiche, and the entrant declines to duel if quiche is observed but duels if beer is observed. • In such an equilibrium, the decision to duel following beer is rationalized by any off-the-equilibrium-path belief that puts sufficiently high probability (at least 1/2) on the incumbent being wimpy given that the non equilibrium choice “beer” has been observed: μ(x|{x,x’}) = μ(W|B)> ½ • But here such beliefs seem unnatural: the prior belief is .9 that the incumbent is surly, but when conditioned on the observation of beer - which is preferred if surly but not if wimpy - the posterior belief is at least .5 that the incumbent is wimpy.

  48. Sequential Equilibria How can we reject the second equilibrium? Using the intuitive criterion one can argue that surly will find it optimal to deviate from the proposed equilibrium: if S is type t’, the following speech should be believed by R: I am t'. To prove this, I am sending m' instead of the equilibrium m. Note that if I were t I would not want to do this, no matter what you might infer from m'. And, as t', I have an incentive to do this provided it convinces you that I am not t. If the entrant concludes that the beer-drinker is surly, then declining to duel is the optimal decision. This yields a payoff of 3 for surly, which is better than the 2 earned in equilibrium.

  49. SIGNALING GAMESEQUILIBRIA and BELIEFSinPOLITICAL ECONOMICS MODELS:THE ACCOUNTABILITY PROBLEM

  50. Accountability and Signalling Games Two models to understand the determinants of good government. The basic idea is that good government is associated with institutions which affects the incentives and the selection of those who make policy decisions. The incentive problem is studied analyzing the possible equilibria of principal-agent models between citizens and government, where the principals are the citizens and the agents are the politicians. The heart of these models is rulers' accountability towards citizens, i.e. the responsibility of rulers as agents towards the citizens and the political elites as principals Whether and how accountability is achieved depends on the rules of the game.

More Related