1 / 12

Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods

MAT 105 Spring 2008. Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods. Which Method to Use?. We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way Which method should we use? Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them, and keep searching for a better way. Arrow’s Theorem.

martinjuan
Download Presentation

Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. MAT 105 Spring 2008 Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods

  2. Which Method to Use? • We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way • Which method should we use? • Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them, and keep searching for a better way

  3. Arrow’s Theorem • In 1951, Kenneth Arrow proved that this search will be in vain • Specifically, he proved that there is no voting system that satisfies all of the following conditions: • is not a dictatorship • voters rank their candidates in order • independence of irrelevant alternatives • Pareto condition

  4. Getting Around Arrow’s Theorem • Instead of giving up hope, we might look for ways around Arrow’s Theorem • Since we know we can’t have a voting method with all of those conditions being true, we might look for one condition to drop • We certainly don’t want a dictatorship or a method that doesn’t satisfy the Pareto condition • If we drop IIA, we could use Borda Count

  5. Dropping Preference Orders • If we drop the preference order condition, we have two options: • allow voters to express less information • allow voters to express more information • These choices lead to approval voting and range voting, respectively

  6. Approval Voting • Voters cast a single vote for each candidate they approve of • The candidate who receives more votes than any other is the winner

  7. Properties of Approval Voting • We can assume that voters are still using (mental) preference lists, but simply have a “cutoff” above which they approve of a candidate and below which they do not • For example, suppose we have two voters both with preference A>B>C>D • One of these voters might approve of A, B, and C, and the other might approve only of A

  8. Approval Conditions • Approval voting does not satisfy the Condorcet winner criterion • Consider the profile shown here, where red indicates that the voter approves of the candidate • A is the Condorcet winner, but B wins the approval vote

  9. Range Voting • Voters rate each candidate on a scale • Examples • scale from 0 to 10 • 1 star to 5 stars • -2 to 2 thumbs • The candidate with the most points wins

  10. Properties of Range Voting • Again we assume that voters are using an internal ranking to cast votes • If a voter likes A more than B, they will give A at least as many points as they give B • However, there are lots of possibilities for how a voter with preference A>B>C>D could fill out a ballot

  11. Range Conditions • Range voting satisfies the Pareto condition • If every voter prefers A over B, then every ballot will give A at least as many points as B, so A’s total will be at least B’s total • The only way this could make B win is if every single voter gave A the same score as B, and A and B tied for the win

  12. Range Conditions • In fact, range voting satisfies many important conditions (though notably not Condorcet winner) • Range voting appears to be the closest to “fair” that we may be able to get

More Related