1 / 57

CS151 Complexity Theory

CS151 Complexity Theory. Lecture 17 May 30, 2019. New topic: relativization and natural proofs. Approaches to open problems. Almost all major open problems we have seen entail proving lower bounds P ≠ NP - P = BPP * L ≠ P - NP = AM * P ≠ PSPACE NC proper BPP ≠ EXP

lucya
Download Presentation

CS151 Complexity Theory

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CS151Complexity Theory Lecture 17 May 30, 2019

  2. New topic: relativization andnatural proofs

  3. Approaches to open problems • Almost all major open problems we have seen entail proving lower bounds • P ≠ NP - P = BPP * • L ≠ P - NP = AM * • P ≠ PSPACE • NC proper • BPP ≠ EXP • PH proper • EXP P/poly • we know circuit lower bounds imply derandomization • more difficult (and recent): derandomization implies circuit lower bounds!

  4. Approaches to open problems • two natural approaches • simulation + diagonalization(uniform) • circuit lower bounds (non-uniform) • no success for either approach as applied to date Why?

  5. Approaches to open problems in a precise, formal sense these approaches are too powerful ! • if they could be used to resolve major open problems, a side effect would be: • proving something that is false, or • proving something that is believed to be false

  6. Relativization • Many proofs and techniques we have seen relativize: • they hold after replacing all TMs with oracle TMs that have access to an oracle A • e.g. LAPAfor all oracles A • e.g.PA ≠ EXPAfor all oracles A

  7. Relativization • Idea: design an oracle A relative to which some statement is false • implies there can be no relativizing proof of that statement • e.g. design A for which PA= NPA • Better: also design an oracle B relative to which statement is true • e.g. also design B for which PB≠ NPB • implies no relativizing proof can resolve truth of the statement either way !

  8. Relativization • Oracles are known that falsify almost every major conjecture concerning complexity classes • for these conjectures, non-relativizing proofs are required • almost all known proofs in Complexity relativize (sometimes after some reformulation) • notable exceptions: • The PCP Theorem • IP = PSPACE • most circuit lower bounds (more on these later)

  9. Oracles for P vs. NP • Goal: • oracle A for which PA = NPA • oracle B for which PB ≠ NPB • conclusion: resolving P vs. NP requires a non-relativizing proof

  10. Oracles for P vs. NP • for PA = NPAneed Ato be powerful • warning: intend to make P more powerful, but also make NP more powerful. • e.g. A = SAT doesn’t work • however A = QSAT works: PSPACEPQSATNPQSAT NPSPACE and we knowNPSPACEPSPACE

  11. Oracles for P vs. NP Theorem: there exists an oracle B for which PB ≠ NPB. • Proof: • define L = {1k : x B s.t. |x| = k} • we will show L NPB – PB. • easy: L NPB(no matter what B is)

  12. Oracles for P vs. NP • design B by diagonalizing against all “PBmachines” • M1, M2, M3, … is an enumeration of deterministic OTMs • each machine appears infinitely often • Biwill be those strings of length iin B • we build Biafter simulating machine Mi

  13. Oracles for P vs. NP L = {1k : x B s.t. |x| = k} • Proof (continued): • maintain “exceptions” X that must not go in B • initially X = { }, B0 = { } Stage i: • simulate Mi(1i) for ilogi steps • when Mi makes an oracle query q: • if |q| < i, answer using Bi-1 • if |q| i, answer “no”; add q to X • if simulated Mi accepts 1i then Bi = Bi-1 • if simulated Mi rejects 1i, Bi = Bi-1 {x {0,1}i : x X}

  14. Oracles for P vs. NP L = {1k : x B s.t. |x| = k} • Proof (continued): • if Mi accepts, we ensure no strings of length i in B • therefore 1i L, and so Mi does not decide L • if Mi rejects, we ensure some string of length i in B • Why? Bi = Bi-1 {x {0,1}i : x X} and |X| is at most Σj ijlog j << 2i • therefore 1iL, and so Mi does not decide L • Conclude: L PB

  15. Circuit lower bounds • Relativizing techniques are out… • but most circuit lower bound techniques do not relativize • exponential circuit lower bounds known for weak models: • e.g. constant-depth poly-size circuits • But, utter failure (so far) for more general models. Why?

  16. Natural Proofs • Razborov and Rudich defined the following “natural” format for circuit lower bounds: • identify property Pof functions f:{0,1}*{0,1} • P = n Pn is a natural property if: • (useful) n fnPnimplies f does not have poly-size circuits [i.e. fnPnimplies ckt size s(n) >> poly(n)] • (constructive) can decide “fnPn?” in poly time given the truth table of fn • (large) at least (½)O(n) fraction of all 22n functions on n bits are in Pn • show some function family g = {gn} is in Pn

  17. Natural Proofs • all known circuit lower bound techniques are natural for a suitably parameterized version of the definition Theorem (RR): if there is a 2n-OWF, then there is no natural property P. • factoring believed to be 2n-OWF • general version also rules out natural properties useful for proving many other separations, under similar cryptographic assumptions

  18. Natural Proofs • Proof: • main idea: natural property Pn can efficiently distinguish pseudorandom functions from truly random functions • but cryptographic assumption implies existence of pseudorandom functions for which this is impossible

  19. Proof (continued) • Recall: assuming One-Way-Permutations fk:{0,1}k{0,1}k that are not invertible by 2ksize circuits • we constructed PRG G:{0,1}k{0,1}2k • no circuit C of size s = 2kfor which |Prx[C(G(x)) = 1] – Prz[C(z) = 1]| > 1/s (BMY construction with slightly modified parameters)

  20. Proof (continued) • Think of G as G:{0,1}k{0,1}k{0,1}k G(x) = (y1, y2) • Graphically: x G y1 y2

  21. Proof (continued) Given x, i, can compute i-th output bit in time npoly(k) • A function F:{0,1}k{0,1}2n (set n = k) x height n-log k G each x, defines a poly-time computable function fx G G G G G G G G G G G G G G

  22. Proof (continued) (useful) n fnPnf does not have poly-size circuits (constructive) “fnPn?” in poly time given truth table of fn (large) at least (½)O(n) fraction of all 22nfns. on n-bits in Pn • fx in poly-time for all x: fxPn(useful) • Prg[g Pn] (1/2)O(n)(large) • constructive: exists circuit T:{0,1}2n{0,1} of size 2O(n) for which |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)

  23. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D0: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  24. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D1: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  25. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D2: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  26. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D3: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  27. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D4: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  28. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D5: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  29. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D6: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  30. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D7: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  31. Proof (continued) • |Prx[T(fx) = 1] – Prg[T(g) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) x distribution D2n/k-1: pick roots of red subtrees independently from {0,1}k G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  32. Proof (continued) • For some i: |Pr[T(Di) = 1] - Pr[T(Di-1) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)/2n = (1/2)O(n) x G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  33. Proof (continued) • For some i: |Pr[T(Di) = 1] - Pr[T(Di-1) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)/2n = (1/2)O(n) x fix values at roots of all other subtrees to preserve difference G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  34. Proof (continued) • For some i: |Pr[T( Di’ ) = 1] - Pr[T( Di-1’ ) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)/2n = (1/2)O(n) x Di’: distribution Di after fixing G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  35. Proof (continued) • For some i: |Pr[T( Di’ ) = 1] - Pr[T( Di-1’ ) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)/2n = (1/2)O(n) x Di-1’: distribution Di-1 after fixing G G G G G G G G G G G G G G G ...

  36. Proof (continued) |Pr[T( Di’ ) = 1] - Pr[T( Di-1’ ) = 1]| (1/2)O(n)/2n = (1/2)O(n) • C(y1,y2)=T( ) |Prx[C(G(x)) = 1] - Pry1, y2[C(y1, y2) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) y1 y2 G G G G G G G G G G G G  T( Di’ ) T( Di-1’ )

  37. Proof (continued) • recall: no circuit C of size s = 2kfor which: |Prx[C(G(x)) = 1] – Pry1, y2[C(y1, y2) = 1]| > 1/s • we have C of size 2O(n) for which: |Prx[C(G(x)) = 1] - Pry1, y2[C(y1, y2) = 1]| (1/2)O(n) • with n = k, arbitrary constant • set such that 2O(n) < s • contradiction.

  38. Natural Proofs • To prove circuit lower bounds, we must either: • Violate largeness: seize upon an incredibly specific feature of hard functions (one not possessed by a random function ! ) • Violate constructivity: identify a feature of hard functions that cannot be computed efficiently from the truth table • no “non-natural property” known for all but the very weakest models…

  39. “We do not conclude that researchers should give up on proving serious lower bounds.Quite the contrary, by classifying a large number of techniques that are unable to do the job, we hope to focus research in a more fruitful direction. Pessimism will only be warranted if a long period of time passes without the discovery of a non-naturalizing lower bound proof.” Rudich and Razborov 1994

  40. “We do not conclude that researchers should give up on proving serious lower bounds. Quite the contrary, by classifying a large number of techniques that are unable to do the job, we hope to focus research in a more fruitful direction.Pessimism will only be warranted if a long period of time passes without the discovery of a non-naturalizing lower bound proof.” Rudich and Razborov 1994

  41. “We do not conclude that researchers should give up on proving serious lower bounds. Quite the contrary, by classifying a large number of techniques that are unable to do the job, we hope to focus research in a more fruitful direction. Pessimism will only be warranted if a long period of time passes without the discovery of a non-naturalizing lower bound proof.” Rudich and Razborov 1994

  42. Moral • To resolve central questions: • avoid relativizing arguments • use PCP theorem and related results • focus on circuits, etc… • avoid constructive arguments • avoid arguments that yield lower bounds for random functions

  43. Course Summary

  44. Course summary • Time and space • hierarchy theorems • FVAL in L • CVAL P-complete • QSAT PSPACE-complete • succinct CVAL EXP-complete

  45. Course summary • Non-determinism • NTIME hierarchy theorem • “NP-intermediate” problems (Ladner’s Theorem) • unary languages (likely) not NP-complete • Savitch’s Theorem • Immerman-Szelepcsényi Theorem Problem sets: • sparse languages (likely) not NP-complete

  46. Course summary • Non-uniformity • formula lower bound (Andreev, Hastad) • monotone circuit lower bound (Razborov) Problem sets: • Barrington’s Theorem • formula lower bound for parity

  47. Course summary • Randomness • polynomial identity testing + Schwartz-Zippel • unique-SAT (Valiant-Vazirani Theorem) • Blum-Micali-Yao PRG • Nisan-Wigderson PRG • worst-case hardness ) average-case hardness • Trevisan extractor Problem sets: • Goldreich-Levin hard bit

  48. Course summary • Alternation • QSATi complete for levels of the PH • Karp-Lipton theorem • BPP in PH Problem sets: • approximate counting + sampling with an NP-oracle • VC-dimension is 3-complete • the class S2P (final)

  49. Course summary • Counting • #matching is #P-complete Problem sets: • permanent is #P-complete • Toda’s theorem: PHP#P

  50. Course summary • Interaction • IP = PSPACE • GI in NPcoAM • using NW PRG for MA, variant for AM • hardness of approximation , PCPs • elements of the PCP theorem Problem sets: • BLR linearity test • Clique hard to approximate to within N

More Related