1 / 41

Econ 522 Economics of Law

This lecture covers formation defenses and performance excuses in contract law, including duress and necessity. It also explores the role of trust in contracts through experimental games.

lindsayj
Download Presentation

Econ 522 Economics of Law

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Econ 522Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2017 Lecture 13

  2. Logistics • Exam will be graded/returned later this week • Homework 3 (contract law) is up – due March 30 • Class will not meet next Wednesday (March 15) • (unless there’s a snow day before then or something)

  3. Last week… • What default rules should fill in the gaps? • C&U: impute the terms the parties would have wanted – allocate each risk to efficient bearer of that risk • (Friedman: several ways to tell who that is) • Ayres & Gertner: use default rules to penalize one or both parties from withholding information • Reasons a contract might not be enforced • Derogation of public policy • Incompetence • but not drunkenness • Today: more reasons a contract might not be enforced • But first…

  4. Another experiment:is trust a problem?

  5. We motivated contracts with an agency (trust) game Player 1 (you) Trust me Don’t Player 2 (me) (100, 0) Share profits Keep all the money (150, 50) (0, 200) • Without binding contracts, might be no reason for me to return your money, so no reason for you to trust me

  6. To see if trust is a problem, we’ll use a similar game as an experiment • Player A starts with $5 • Chooses how much of it to give to player B • That money is quadrupled • Player B has $5, plus 4x whatever A gave him/her • Chooses how much (if any) to give back to player A • So for example… • if player A decides to send $3… • then B has $5 + $12 = $17, and can send A any amount up to 17 and keep the rest… • …and A ends up with $2 plus whatever B sends

  7. To see if trust is a problem, we’ll use a similar game as an experiment Player 1 Send 0 Send 5 x Player 2 Return 0 Return 5 + 4x y ((5 – x) + y, (5 + 4x) – y) • Player 1 gets whatever he kept, plus whatever 2 sends him • Player 2 gets 5, plus four times what 1 sends him, minus whatever he sends to player 1

  8. We’ll try this game three different ways • Anonymously – A and B don’t know who each other are • we’ll use student ID numbers to identify players, and play on paper • Privately – A and B don’t interact, but will learn who each other are after the game • still on paper, but with names, so B sees A’s name • after class, I’ll email A and B with each others’ names • Publicly – A and B play out loud in front of the class

  9. Back to work:formation defenses andperformance excuses

  10. Two ways to try to get out of a contract • Formation defense • Claim that a valid contract does not exist • (Example: no consideration) • Performance excuse • Yes, a valid contract was created • But circumstances have changed and I should be allowed to not perform without penalty • Last week, we saw incompetence, a formation defense • No meeting of the minds  no valid contract • But, being drunk isn’t a valid excuse!

  11. Another formation defense: dire constraints • Necessity • I’m about to starve, someone offers me a sandwich for $10,000 • My boat’s about to sink, someone offers me a ride to shore for $1,000,000 • Contract would not be upheld: I signed it out of necessity • Duress • Other party is responsible for situation I’m in • “I made him an offer he couldn’t refuse” • Contract signed at gunpoint would not belegally enforceable

  12. Duress source: http://news.yahoo.com/man-sues-former-hostages-says-broke-promise-190902970.html

  13. Friedman on duress • Example • Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $1000 • You write him a check • Do you have to honor the agreement? • “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” • He did – he wants your $1000 • You did – you’d rather pay $1000 than be killed • So why not enforce it? • Makes muggings more profitable  leads to more muggings • Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior

  14. Friedman on duress • Example • Mugger threatens to kill you unless you give him $1000 • You write him a check • Do you have to honor the agreement? • “Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable” • He did – he wants your $100 • You did – you’d rather pay $100 than be killed • So why not enforce it? • Makes muggings more profitable  leads to more muggings • Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade, in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior

  15. What about necessity? • Same logic doesn’t work for necessity • You get caught in a storm on your $1,000,000 sailboat • Tugboat offers to tow you to shore for $900,000 • (Otherwise he’ll save your life but let your boat sink) • Duress: if we enforce contract, incentive for more crimes • Necessity: if we enforce contract, incentive for more tugboats to be available to rescue sailboats • Why is that bad?

  16. What about necessity? “Should I motor around looking for sailboats to save?” • Social cost = private cost = value of my time • Social benefit = probability x (value of boat – cost of tow) • Private benefit = probability x (price I can charge – cost of tow) • If tugboat captain can charge the whole value of the boat, he spends efficient amount of time saving sailboats! • So maybe we should enforce this contract…

  17. What about necessity? “Should I sail today?” • Suppose tugboat is there to rescue me if there’s a storm • Social benefit = private benefit = how much I enjoy sailing • Social cost = probability x cost of tow • Private cost = probability x price he can charge • If tugboat captain can only charge cost of tow, I sail efficient amount • If he can charge the whole value of the boat, I undersail!

  18. Friedman’s point • Same transaction sets incentives on both parties • Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other • “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” • Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle • And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm!

  19. Friedman’s point • Same transaction sets incentives on both parties • Price that would be efficient for one decision, is inefficient for other • “Put the incentive where it would do the most good” • Least inefficient price is somewhere in the middle • And probably not the price that would be negotiated in the middle of a storm! • So makes sense for courts to overturn contracts signed under necessity, replace them with ex-ante optimal terms • More general point • Single price creates multiple incentives • May be impossible to get efficient behavior in all dimensions

  20. Real duress versus fake duress • Court won’t enforce contracts signed under threat of harm • “Give me $100 or I’ll shoot you” • But many negotiations contain threats • “Give me a raise, or I’ll quit” • “$3,000 is my final offer for the car, take it or I walk” • The difference? • Threat of destruction of value versus failure to create value • A promise is enforceable if extracted as price of cooperating in creating value; not if it was extracted by threat to destroy value

  21. Example: Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (US Ct App 1902) • Captain hires crew in Seattle for fishing expedition to Alaska • In Alaska, crew demands higher wages or they’ll quit, captain agrees • Back in Seattle, captain refuses to pay the higher wages, claiming he agreed to them under duress • Court ruled for captain • Since crew had already agreed to do the work, no new consideration was given for promise of higher wage

  22. A performance excuse:impossibility

  23. Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility • When performance becomes impossible, should promisor owe damages, or be excused from performing? • A perfect contract would explicitly state who bears each risk • Contract may give clues as to how gaps should be filled • Industry custom might be clear • But in some cases, court must fill gap

  24. Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility • In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach • But there are exceptions • Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made”

  25. Next doctrine for voiding a contract: impossibility • In most situations, when neither contract nor industry norm offers guidance, promisor is held liable for breach • But there are exceptions • Change “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made” • Efficiency requires assigning liability to the party that can bear the risk at least cost • We’ve seen several ways to determine who that is

  26. That’s why Hadley v Baxendale was “surprising” • Baxendale (shipper) could influence speed of delivery, Hadley could not • So Baxendale was efficient bearer of the risk of delay • Court ruled he didn’t owe damages for lost profits, forcing Hadley to bear much of this risk • Only makes sense as a “penalty default” • Rule creates incentive for Hadley to reveal urgency of this shipment

  27. Contracts based onbad information

  28. Contracts based on faulty information • Four doctrines for invalidating a contract • Fraud • Failure to disclose (sometimes) • Frustration of purpose • Mutual mistake

  29. Fraud • Fraud: one party was deliberately tricked source: http://www.wyff4.com/r/29030818/detail.html

  30. What if you trick someone by withholding information? • It depends • Under the civil law, there is a duty to disclose • If you fail to supply information you should have, contract will be voided – failure to disclose • Under the common law, less so • Seller has to share information about hidden dangers… • …but generally not information that makes a product less valuable without making it dangerous • Exception: new products come with “implied warranty of fitness” • Another exception: Obde v Schlemeyer

  31. Duty to disclose under common law • Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information • But… • Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA) • Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer • Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage • Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages)

  32. Duty to disclose under common law • Under common law, seller required to inform buyer about hidden safety risks, generally not other information • But… • Obde v Schlemeyer (1960, Sup Ct of WA) • Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer • Termites should have been exterminated immediately to prevent further damage • Court in Obde imposed duty to disclose (awarded damages) • Some states require used car dealers to reveal major repairs done, sellers of homes to reveal certain types of defects…

  33. Failure to disclose? source: http://kdvr.com/2012/10/26/chinese-man-sues-wife-for-being-ugly-wins-120000/

  34. What if both parties were misinformed? Frustration of Purpose • Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless • Coronation Cases • “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost”

  35. What if both parties were misinformed? Frustration of Purpose • Change in circumstance made the original promise pointless • Coronation Cases • “When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost” Mutual Mistake • Mutual mistake about facts • Circumstances had already changed, but we didn’t know • Logger buys land with timber on it, but forest fire had wiped out the timber the week before • Mutual mistake about identity • Disagreement over what was being sold

  36. Another principle for allocating risks efficiently: uniting knowledge and control • Hadley v Baxendale (miller and shipper) • Hadley knew shipment was time-critical • But Baxendale was deciding how to ship crankshaft (boat or train) • Party that had information was not the party making decisions • Efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control • Contracts that unite knowledge and control are generally efficient, should be upheld • Contracts that separate knowledge and control may be inefficient, should more often be set aside

  37. What About Unilateral Mistake? • Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information • Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control • Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information • I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless • You sell it to me at a low price • Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld

  38. What About Unilateral Mistake? • Mutual mistake: neither party had correct information • Contract neither united nor separated knowledge and control • Unilateral mistake: one party has mistaken information • I know your car is a valuable antique, you think it’s worthless • You sell it to me at a low price • Contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally upheld • Contracts based on unilateral mistake generally unite knowledge and control • And, enforcing them creates an incentive to gather information

  39. Unilateral mistake: Laidlaw v Organ (U.S. Supreme Court, 1815) • War of 1812: British blockaded port of New Orleans • Price of tobacco fell, since it couldn’t be exported • Organ (tobacco buyer) learned the war was over • Immediately negotiated with Laidlaw firm to buy a bunch of tobacco at the depressed wartime price • Next day, news broke the war had ended, price of tobacco went up, Laidlaw sued • Supreme Court ruled that Organ was not required to communicate his information

  40. Uniting knowledge and control • Laidlaw v. Organ established: contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally valid • Agrees with efficiency: these contracts typically unite knowledge and control • What about Obde v. Schlemeyer? • The termites case was based on unilateral mistake • Court still upheld contract, but punished seller for hiding information • In that case, contract separated knowledge from control

  41. Unilateral mistake: productive versus redistributive information • Productive information: information that can be used to produce more wealth • Redistributive information: information that can be used to redistribute wealth in favor of informed party • Cooter and Ulen • Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of productive information should be enforced… • …especially if that knowledge was the result of active investment • Contracts based on one party’s knowledge of purely redistributive information, or fortuitously acquired information, should not be enforced

More Related