1 / 39

The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language

The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language. Systematicity. Introduced in Fodor & Pylyshyn (1988): A feature of cognition, inferential coherence ``The ability to produce/understand some sentences is intrinsically connected to the ability to produce/understand certain others. ‘’ (p. 37)

jnestor
Download Presentation

The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. The Nature of Systematicity in Natural Language

  2. Systematicity • Introduced in Fodor & Pylyshyn (1988): • A feature of cognition, inferential coherence • ``The ability to produce/understand some sentences is intrinsically connected to the ability to produce/understand certain others. ‘’ (p. 37) • Fodor & Pylyshyn give no clear definition (see van Gelder) and only two examples Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  3. The operationalization of systematicity • When an agent understands the sentence Peter likes Maria, she understands the sentence Maria likes Peteras well. • When an agent understands the expressions brown triangleand black square, she understands the expressions brown squareand black triangleas well. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  4. Outline • What is systematicity? • and to what degree is our understanding systematic • Does compositionality entail systematicity? • No, because • context-dependence of meaning • intrusion of encyclopedic knowledge on language understanding • What are appropriate models of natural language understanding if systematicity is taken into account ? Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  5. Is our understanding systematic ? • Do all who understand good writer and bad teacher also understand bad writer and good teacher? • Do all who understand within an hour and without a watch also understand within a watch and without an hour? (Szabó 2004). • Does a child who understands Mom drives me to kindergarten also understand I drive mom to kindergarten? Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  6. Understanding not Systematic • Language understanding is not completely systematic. • This is because the world is not entirely systematic • A. Clark (1996) ``Instead of treating [systematicity] as a property to be directly induced by a canny choice of basic architecture, it may be fruitful to try to treat it as intrinsic to the knowledge we want a system to acquire. • A good model of language • explains the systematic patterns of our language understanding • gives an account of when and why we find patterns that are not really predictable. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  7. Does compositionality entail systematicity? • Compositionality: The meaning of a compound expression is determined by the meanings of its constituents and the syntactic way these constituents are combined. • Systematicity: there are predictable patterns among the sentences we understand. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  8. The present position • Compositionality does not entail systematicity • Systematicity is possible without compositionality Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  9. How to derive systematicity? • Fodor & Pylyshyn: • in the presented case the systematicity of linguistic competence derives from the fact that the syntactic operation of modification relates to the semantic operation of conjunction (or intersection) Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  10. Understanding NL Expressions • According to the classical view, the phrase 'understanding natural language expressions' means more than just fixing a denotation. • We 'understand' a phrase as brown triangleif (i) we are able to grasp the corresponding conceptual representation (browntriangle) (ii) the corresponding conceptual components have an known truth functional content (iii) With the help of the involved logical operators it is possible to determine the truth conditions of the whole phrase under discussion Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  11. Sytematicity Clauses: A sample “derivation” • understanding the expressions brown triangle and black square • deriving browntriangle and blacksquare • extracting the lexicon entries brown brown, blackblack, triangletriangle, squaresquare. • calculating the corresponding conceptual representations for brown square and black triangle : brownsquare and blacktriangle • can get the truth-conditional impact of these forms • we understand the expressions brown square and black triangle Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  12. But does this actually work? • This proposal doesn’t work for even the simplest of adjective-noun combinations • Intersection doesn’t give you the systematic inferences that you would expect or would desire Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  13. Why compositionality fails to explain systematicity Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  14. Context dependence • In his “Grundlagen der Mathematik” Frege (1884) noticed the context-dependence of words (and took this as a argument against compositionality in NL) “One should ask for the meaning of a word only in the context of a sentence, and not in isolation“ • There are compositional models of semantics that take context dependence into account • We can use the phenomenon of context-dependence for construing an argument against deriving systematicity from compositionality. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  15. What is a white triangle? A The white triangle A The black triangle From P. Bosch (2002)Explaining semantic productivity. Paper presented at the Symposium on Logic and Creativity: Integrating Categorial Rules and Experience, Osnabrück. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  16. Context Dependence? Does the proposition expressed by ‘black triangle’ depend on the contrast set? Answer 1: No. The contrast set is relevant only for choosing a good/appropriate/optimal referring expression PROBLEM: ? Triangle 1 is black and white(in one and the same respect) Answer 2: Yes. Context-dependency of utterance meaning is widely accepted and also applies here (Kaplan’s characters; Haas-Spohn’s ‘hidden indexicality’; e.g. in connection with natural kind terms like water; theories of underspecification, e.g. Carstons 2002; explicatures in relevance theory) Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  17. What is a red apple? (a) a red apple [red peel] (b) a sweet apple [sweet pulp] (c) a reddish grapefruit [reddish pulp] (d) a white room/ a white house [inside/outside] A red apple? No, it’s a green apple but it’s red on the inside Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  18. More examples • Quine (1960) was the first who noted the contrast between red apple (red on the outside) and pink grapefruit (pink on the inside). • In a similar vein, Lahav (1993) argues that an adjective such as brown doesn’t make a simple and fixed contribution to any composite expression in which it appears: In order for a cow to be brown most of its body’s surface should be brown, though not its udders, eyes, or internal organs. A brown crystal, on the other hand, needs to be brown both inside and outside. A brown book is brown if its cover, but not necessarily its inner pages, are mostly brown, while a newspaper is brown only if all its pages are brown. For a potato to be brown it needs to be brown only outside, ... (Lahav 1993: 76). Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  19. Three consequences • Intersectivity, ||A(B)|| = ||A()||||B||,doesn’t hold for most ‘absolute’ adjectives and Fodor & Pylyshyn's compositional analysis breaks down • Systematicity statements cannot be derived from compositionality if intersectivity fails • Encyclopedic knowledge is required to determine the truth conditional content of an utterance (explicaturein Relevance Theory) • When an agent understands the expressions red apple (RED PEEL) and sweet grapefruit (SWEET PULP), then it's likely that she understands red grapefruit (RED PULP) and sweet apple (SWEET PULP) as well. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  20. The Theoretical Part Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  21. Approach 1: The underspecification view • Radical underspecification augmented with contextual enrichment • smallx small(x,N) *small terrier x [small(x,N) & terrier(x)] • Analogously for red apple with place-holders for the relevant partsred  x [part(Y,x) & red(Y)]red apple x [part(Y,x) & red(Y) & apple(x)] • How to determine the proper values for N and Y, respectively? * with small(x,N)  size(x) < N Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  22. A mechanism of contextual enrichment • The variables are specified in a way that maximizes the relevance of the corresponding question • Small Terrier: Is a (randomly selected) terrier smaller than N? • Red Apple: What color is part Y (of a randomly selected apple)? • Probabilistic Theory of Relevance, see Robert van Rooy (2000): Comparing Questions and Answers: A bit of Logic, a bit of Language, and some bits of Information Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  23. Entropy of a question • The semantic value of a question Q is a partition {q1, ..., qn} of the domain Ω. •  inf(q) = -log2 prob(q)information = measure of surprise • Entropy of a question Q • The entropy of a question expresses our uncertainty about the answer. Good questions have high entropies Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  24. What is a black triangle? Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  25. What is a red apple? A red apple? What color is an apple? Q1 What color is its peel? Q2 What color is its pulp? E(Q1) >> E(Q2) Color differences between apples are expected for the peel and not for the pulp. Therefore, the presented apple is considered as a green apple (inside red) and not as a red apple (outside green).This can change if we update our probability distribution. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  26. Problems with the underspecification view • Requires rather clumsy lexical entries • How much of the peel of an apple has to be red in order to call it a red peel? • This theory does not really clarify how the border line between the underspecified representation and the contextual enrichment is ever to be determined Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  27. Approach 2: Adnominal functors • Take Montague (1970) as its starting-point and take adjectives as adnominal functors. • red(X) means roughly the property • (a) of having a red inner volume if X denotes fruits only the inside of which is edible • (b) of having a red surface if X denotes fruits with edible outside • (c) of having a functional part that is red if X denotes tools, … Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  28. Montague and systematicity clauses • We cannot derive the intended systematicity clauses if we realize compositionality via adnominal functors! • f(a) = p, g(b) = q f(b) = ?, g(a) = ? • Compositionality is often very simple to realize if (higher order) functions are introduced • In many cases, this idea realizes generalizations to the worst case • Unfortunately, we cannot derive interesting systematicity clauses from this style of compositionality! Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  29. Constraining the models • Additional constraints are required that restrict the set of possible models • I will assume that these constraints can be extracted from a Bayesian picture of the mental encyclopedia • This is not so different from assuming a system of violable constraints (ranked defaults instead of inviolable meaning postulates) • Systematicity mainly results from these additional constraints! Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  30. Approach 3: Connectionst model of adjectival modification* • Overcoming the gap between compositionality and systematicity • Modeling both the truth-functional aspects of adjectival modification and the typicality effects (Kamp & Partee 1995) • Connectionist variant of the selective modification model of Smith et al. (1988) • It shares with this model the (localist) attribute-value representation for the prototypes (apple, grapefruit, …) and for the relevant instances. * From Blutner, Hendriks, de Hoop, & Schwartz (to appear): When compositionality fails to predict systematicity Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  31. Adjective Noun • Color • Taste • Form Conceptual Layer The simplified model Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  32. Conclusions • Systematicity of natural language understanding is intimately related to knowledge about the world • Systematicity clauses have to reflect this reality • A compositional representational system doesn’t give you systematicity of understanding because context-dependency of lexical meaning and world-knowledge both affect understanding Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  33. Conclusions cont. (4) If lexical principles like “intersectivity” fail (because of context dependency) systematicity clauses can no longer be derived from compositionality (5) A Bayesian and/or connectionist picture of the mental encyclopedia is the key for deriving systematicity clauses! (6) The principle of compositionality of meaning may be interesting  not as part of cognitive architecture, but as a consequence of evolutionary learning (e.g. Kirby). Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  34. Thank you for your attention Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  35. ... other problems with adjectival modification Typicality effects The problems of typicality don't relate to the truth-conditional impact of adjectival modification. However, a good model should account for both effects: the truth-conditional peculiarities of adjectival modification and the typicality effects. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  36. The red hair problem • Quine (1960): the different colors typically denoted (strong preference) by red in red apple and red hair • In Japanese, aka-zatoo 'brown sugar' (lit. 'red sugar') comes in the same range of colors as shira-miso, lit. 'white bean paste‘ • the actual color value deviates in a systematic way from the prototypical color value that can be assigned to the color adjective in isolation – in dependency on the conceptual properties of the modified noun Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  37. The pet fish problem • Goldfish is a poorish example of a fish, and a poorish example of a pet, but it's quite a good example of a pet fish (the conjunction effect of typicality: cx(A&B) > cx(B)) • In case of "incompatible conjunctions" such as pet fish, striped apple or brown apple the conjunction effect is greater than in "compatible conjunctions“ (red apple). Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  38. Prototype effects • Using Tversky's (1977) contrast rule (formulated for activation vectors) sim(s,t) = i min(si,ti) i |siti| • sim(sred apple,t1) > sim(sapple, t1) • sim(sbrown apple,t2)sim(sapple,t2) > sim(sred apple,t1)sim(sapple,t1) Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

  39. Next steps • Extend the model by distinguish different parts of the fruits (inside and outside) • Since without further learning the model starts with a uniform weight matrix, we expect that the 'neutral' force of modification affects all parts uniformly • After learning, that the color of the outside of fruits is more discriminating than the color of its inside, we expect that the learning mechanism correctly reproduces the expected sort of modification • Similarities to Zwarts' (2003) "strongest meaning" model which starts with an initial default hypothesis which is subsequentially modified if more encyclopedic knowledge comes in. Blutner & Spenader KNAW-Colloquium

More Related