1 / 32

Introduction to decision analysis

Introduction to decision analysis. Jouni Tuomisto THL. Q R A. Decision analysis is done for purpose: to inform and thus improve action. Decisions by an individual vs. in a society.

conan-ortiz
Download Presentation

Introduction to decision analysis

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Introduction to decision analysis Jouni Tuomisto THL

  2. Q R A Decision analysis is done for purpose: to inform and thus improve action

  3. Decisions by an individual vs. in a society • In theory, decision analysis is straightforward with a single decision-maker: she just has to assess her subjective probabilities and utilities and maximize expected utility. • In practice, there are severe problems: assessing probabilities and utilities is difficult. • However, in a society things become even more complicated: • There are several participants in decision-making. • There is disagreement about probabilities and utilities. • The decision models used are different. • The knowledge bases are different. NOTE! In this course, "knowledge" means both scientific (what is?) and ethical (what should be?) knowledge.

  4. Probability of an event x Prize p Red Red ball 100 € • If you are indifferent between decisions 1 and 2, then your probability of x is p=R/N. Decision 1 White ball 0 € 1-p x happens 100 € Decision 2 0 € x does not happen

  5. Outcome measures in decision analysis

  6. Outcome measures in decision analysis • DALY: disability-adjusted life year • QALY: quality-adjusted life year • WTP: willingness to pay • Utility

  7. Disability-adjusted life year • The disability-adjusted life year (DALY) is a measure of overall disease burden, expressed as the number of years lost due to ill-health, disability or early death. (Wikipedia) • Originates from WHO to measure burden of disease in several countries in the world.

  8. DALYs in the world 2004 • Source: Wikipedia

  9. How to calculate DALYs • DALY= YLL+YLD • YLL=Years of life lost • YLD=Years lived with disability • YLD = #cases*severity weight*duration of disase • More DALYs is worse.

  10. Disability weights • http://en.opasnet.org/w/Disability_weights

  11. Weighting of DALYs • Discounting • present value Wt = Wt+n*(r+1)-n • Where W is weight, r is discount rate, and n is number of years into the future and t is current time • Typically, r is something like 3 %/year. • Age weighting • W = 0.1658 Ye-0.04 Y • where W is weight and Y is age in years

  12. Discounting Wt = Wt+n (1+r)-n

  13. Age weighting with DALYsW = 0.1658 Ye-0.04 Y

  14. Estimating QALY weights • Time-trade-off (TTO): Choose between: • remaining in a state of ill health for a period of time, • being restored to perfect health but having a shorter life expectancy. • Standard gamble (SG): • Choose between: • remaining in a state of ill health for a period of time, • a medical intervention which has a chance of either restoring them to perfect health, or killing them. • Visual analogue scale (VAS): Rate a state of ill health on a scale from 0 to 100, with 0 representing death and 100 representing perfect health.

  15. QALY weight of disease x (standard gamble) Adjust u in such a way that you are indifferent between decisions 1 and 2. Then, your QALY weight is u(x). Utility Disease ? Live with disease Healthy u 1 Treatment 0 Dead 1-u

  16. Standard descriptions for QALYs • E.g. as the EuroQol Group's EQ5D questionnaire • Categorises health states according to the following dimensions: • mobility, • self-care, • usual activities (e.g. work, study, homework or leisure activities), • pain/discomfort • anxiety/depression.

  17. Measuring utilities Adjust u in such a way that you are indifferent between the two options. Then, your utility for option x is u(x). Utility Option ? Choose option x Best outcome u 1 Choose gamble 0 Worst outcome 1-u

  18. Utility of money is not linear

  19. CAFE clean air for Europe

  20. Value of statistical life VSL • Measure the willingness to accept slightly higher mortality risk. • E.g. a worker wants 50 € higher salary per month as a compensation for a work which has 0.005 chance of fatal injury in 10 years. • 50 €/mo*12 mo/a*10 a / 0.005 = 1200000 € / fatality • VSL is the marginal value of a small increment in risk. Of course, it does NOT imply that a person’s life is worth VSL. • A similar measure: VOLY = value of life year.

  21. The ultimate decision criterion: expected utility • Max(E(u(dj)))=Maxj (∑i u(dj,θi) p(θi) ) • Calculate the expected utility for each decision d option j. • Pick the one with highest expected utility.

  22. Which option is the best? Utility Swine flu 0.03 0.3 Healthy 1 Vaccination 0.003 Side effect 0 Swine flu 0.3 0.15 Do nothing 1 Healthy

  23. Which option is the best? u(Vaccination)=0.976 u(Do nothing)=0.895 Choose vaccination u; E(u) Swine flu 0.03 0.3;0.009 Healthy 1;0.967 Vaccination 0.003 Side effect 0;0 Swine flu 0.3;0.045 0.15 Do nothing 1;0.85 Healthy

  24. Limitations of decision trees A decision tree becomes quickly increasingly complex. This only contains two uncertain variables and max three outcomes of a variable. Swine flu 0.03 Complications Vaccination 0.003 Swine flu 0.15 Complications Do nothing Healthy

  25. Causal diagrams: a powerful tool for describing decision analysis models Swine flu Outcome Vaccination Complications

  26. Bayesian belief networks • Arrows are causal dependencies described by conditional probabilities. • P(swine flu | vaccination) • P(complications | swine flu) • P(outcome | swine flu, complicatons) • These probabilities describe the whole model.

  27. Functional models • Arrows are causal dependencies described by (deterministic) functions. • swine flu = f1(vaccination) • complications = f2(swine flu) • outcome = f3(swine flu, complicatons) • These functions describe the whole model.

  28. Functional vs. probabilistic dependency • Va1=2.54*Ch1^2 Va2=normal(2.54*Ch1^2,2)

  29. Estimating societal costs of health impacts • In theory, all costs should be estimated. • In practice, the main types considered include • Health case costs (medicine, treatment…). • Loss of productivity (absence from work, school). • WTP of the person to avoid the disease. • The societal cost of disease to other people (relatives etc) is NOT considered.

  30. St Petersburg paradox • Consider the following game of chance: you pay a fixed fee to enter and then a fair coin is tossed repeatedly until a tail appears, ending the game. The pot starts at 1 dollar and is doubled every time a head appears. You win whatever is in the pot after the game ends. Thus you win 1 dollar if a tail appears on the first toss, 2 dollars if a head appears on the first toss and a tail on the second, 4 dollars if a head appears on the first two tosses and a tail on the third, 8 dollars if a head appears on the first three tosses and a tail on the fourth, etc. In short, you win 2k−1 dollars if the coin is tossed k times until the first tail appears. • What would be a fair price to pay for entering the game? • Solved by Daniel Bernoulli, 1738

  31. St Petersburg paradox (2) • To answer this we need to consider what would be the average payout: With probability 1/2, you win 1 dollar; with probability 1/4 you win 2 dollars; with probability 1/8 you win 4 dollars etc. The expected value is thus

  32. Example of a model with causal diagram • Dampness and asthma

More Related