1 / 16

Agreeing on a Value

Agreeing on a Value. James B. Elsner and Thomas H. Jagger Department of Geography, Florida State University. Material based on notes from a one-day short course on Bayesian modeling and prediction given by David Draper (http://www.ams.ucsc.edu/~draper). Quantification of uncertainty

Download Presentation

Agreeing on a Value

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Agreeing on a Value James B. Elsner and Thomas H. Jagger Department of Geography, Florida State University Material based on notes from a one-day short course on Bayesian modeling and prediction given by David Draper (http://www.ams.ucsc.edu/~draper)

  2. Quantification of uncertainty At least three definitions of probability are accepted: classical, frequentist, and Bayesian. Consider the problem of screening for HIV. Widespread screening for HIV has been proposed by some people in some countries (e.g., the U.S.) Two blood tests that screen for HIV are widely available: ELISA—relatively inexpensive (roughly $20) and fairly accurate. Western Blot (WB)—considerably more accurate, but cost quite a bit more (about $100).

  3. A new patient comes to You, a physician, with symptoms that suggest he may be HIV positive (You = a generic person making assessments of uncertainty). Questions: • Is it appropriate to use the language of probability to quantify Your uncertainty about the proposition A = {This patient is HIV positive}? • If so, what kinds of probability are appropriate, and how would You assess P(A) in each case? • What strategy (e.g., ELISA, WB, both?) should You employ to decrease Your uncertainty about A? If You decide to run a screening test, how should Your uncertainty be updated in light of the test results?

  4. Statistics might be defined as the study of uncertainty: how to measure it, and what to do about it, and probability as the part of mathematics (and philosophy) devoted to the quantification of uncertainty. The systematic study of probability is rather recent in the history of ideas, dating back, according to Hacking (1975) to about 1650. Since then three main ways to define probability have been accepted. • Classical: Count elemental outcomes (EOs) in a way that makes them equipossible (e.g., assumption of symmetry). Then compute PC(A) = ratio of nA= number of EOs favorable to A) to n = (total number of EOs).

  5. Example of classical definition: probability of picking a club card from an ordinary deck of cards. In this case, nA= 13 and n = 52, so Pc(A) = 13/52 = 0.25 or 25%. • Frequentist: Restrict attention to attributes of A of events: phenomena that are inherently repeatable under “identical” conditions. Then define PF(A) = limiting value of relative frequency with which A occurs as the number of repetitions approaches infinity. Example of frequentist definition: probability of a hurricane striking Florida in any given year. Compute the relative frequency in say 100 years by counting the number of hurricanes that struck (say 30). We assume that each year is “identical” so the relative rate is 0.3, which gives a limiting probability of at least one hurricane each year of 26% (Poisson assumption).

  6. Personal, or Subjective, or Bayesian: Imagine betting someone about the truth of proposition A, and ask Yourself what odds OYou(in favor of A) You would need to give or receive in order that You judge the bet fair; then (for You) PB:You(A) = OYou / (1 + OYou). Note: If you think the odds are 2:1 in your favor, then PB:You(A) = 2 / 3 = 67%. Besides the classical, frequentist, and Bayesian approaches to defining probability, there are others including the logical (Jeffreys 1961) and fiducial (Fisher 1935).

  7. Strengths and weaknesses: Each of these probability definitions has general advantages and disadvantages. • Classical: • Plus: Simple, when applicable such as idealized coin tossing, drawing colored balls from urns, etc. • Minus: The only way to define “equipossible” without circular appeal to probability is through the principle of insufficient reason—You judge EOs equipossible if You have no grounds (empirical, local, or symmetrical) for favoring one over another. However, this leads to to paradoxes (e.g., assertion of equal uncertainty is not invariant to the choice of scale on which it's asserted).

  8. Frequentist • Plus: Mathematics is relatively tractable. • Minus: Only applies to inherently repeatable events, e.g., PF(George W. Bush will be re-elected in November) is (strictly speaking) undefined. • Bayesian • Plus: All forms of uncertainty are in principle quantifiable with this approach. • Minus: There's no guarantee that the answer You get by querying Yourself about betting odds will retrospectively be seen by You or others as “good” (Hmmm…how should the quality of an uncertainty assessment be judged?).

  9. Application to HIV Screening P(A) = P(this patient is HIV-positive) = ? Data are available from medical journals on prevalence of HIV-positivity in various subsets of P ={all humans}. For example it is higher in gay people and lower in older people. All three probabilistic approaches require You to use Your judgment to identify the recognizable subpopulation. Call this recognizable subpopulationPthis patient. In our casePthis patient is the smallest subset to which this patient belongs for which HIV prevalence differs from that in the rest ofP by an amount You judge as large enough to matter in a practical sense.

  10. Within Pthis patient You regard HIV prevalence as close enough to constant that the differences aren't worth bothering over, but the differences between HIV prevalenceinPthis patient and its complement (notPthis patient) matter to You. Here Pthis patient might consist of everybody who matches this patient on for example, gender, age (category, e.g., 25-29), and sexual orientation. ImportantNote: This is a modeling choice based on judgment; different reasonable people might make different choices; thus probability modeling in the real world is inherently subjective.

  11. As a classicist You would then: a) Use the definition to establish equipossibility within Pthis patient. b) CountnA = (number of HIV-positive people inPthis patient). c) Compute Pc(A) = nA/n. As a frequentist You would: a) Equate P(A) to P(a person chosen at random with replacement (i.e., independent identically distributed (IID) sampling from Pthis patient is HIV positive). b) Imagine repeating this random sampling indefinitely. c) Conclude that the limiting value of the relative frequency of HIV-positivity in these repetitions is PF(A) = nA/n.

  12. Important Note: Strictly speaking we’re not allowed in the frequentist approach to talk about P(This patient is HIV positive)---either he is or he isn’t. Within the frequentist paradigm, we can only talk about the process of sampling people like him from Pthis patient. As a Bayesian, with the information given here You would regard this patient as exchangeable with all other patients in Pthis patient meaning (informally) that You judge Yourself equally uncertain about HIV-positivity for all the patients in this set—and this judgment, together with the axioms of coherence, would also yield: PB:You(A) = nA/n.

  13. Exchangeability and coherence in Bayesian analysis replace the notions of independent and identically distributed from the frequentist approach. Note that, with the same information base, the three approaches in this case have led to the same answer. However…the meaning of that answer depends on the approach. Frequentist probability describes the process of observing a repeatable event. Bayesian probability is an attempt to quantify Your uncertainty about something, repeatable or not.

  14. Subjectivity and Objectivity The classical and frequentist approaches have sometimes been called objective, whereas the Bayesian approach is clearly subjective. Since objectivity sounds like a good goal in science—this has sometimes been used as a claim that the classical and frequentist approaches are superior. Bayesians counter with the argument that in interesting applied problems of realistic complexity, the judgment of equivalence or similarity (equipossible, IID, exchangeability) that is central to all three theories makes them all subjective in practice.

  15. Imagine, for instance, that You are given data on HIV prevalence in a large group of people, along with many variables (possible factors, e.g., age, sex, lifestyle, etc.) that might or might not be relevant to identifying the recognizable subpopulations. You and other reasonable people working independently might well differ in your judgments on which of these factors (predictors) are relevant (and how they should be used in making the prediction), and the results could easily be noticeable variation in the estimates of P(HIV positive). Even if You and other people all attempt so called “objective” methods to arrive at these judgments, there are many such methods and they don’t always lead to the same conclusions.

  16. Thus, the assessment of complicated probabilities (all interesting ones are) is inherently subjective—there are “judgment calls” built into probabilistic and statistical analysis. With this in mind attention in all three approaches should shift away from trying to achieve “objectivity” toward two things: 1) the explicit statement of the assumptions and judgments, so that others may consider their plausibility, and 2) sensitivity analyses exploring the mapping from assumptions to conclusions. To a Bayesian, saying that PB(A) is objective just means that lots of people more or less agree on its value.

More Related